When God
is
the Legislator
Two of the legal systems we have
looked at claim to
be based on rules laid down by GodÑJewish law on the Torah,
Islamic law
on the Koran and the (divinely inspired) practice of the
Prophet Mohammed. That
claim raises problems which are absent, or at least less
serious, in legal
systems based on the decisions of a ruler or legislator.
Similar problems occur
with a system such as U.S. Constitutional law. The
Constitution does not claim
to be divinely inspired, but in U.S. Legal culture it is often
treated as if it
were; although it is possible to change it through human
action, the process is
cumbersome.
One of the problems occurs when God
gets it wrong,
when the humans implementing the legal system are reluctant or
unwilling to go
along with some of its commands. Consider, for one striking
example, the
instructions in Deuteronomy (21:18-21) for dealing with a
disobedient son:
ÒIf a man
have a stubborn
and rebellious son, which will not obey the voice of his
father, or the voice
of his mother, and that, when they have chastened him, will
not hearken unto
them: Then shall his father and his mother lay hold on him,
and bring him out
unto the elders of his city, and unto the gate of his place;
And they shall say
unto the elders of his city, This our son is stubborn and
rebellious, he will
not obey our voice; he is a glutton, and a drunkard. And all
the men of his
city shall stone him with stones, that he die:Ó
The
punishment seems a
little extreme, not only to modern sentiments but to ancient
sentiments as
well. If it is, however, God's command, what is one to do?
A similar
issue is raised
for Muslims by Koran 5:38, which establishes the punishment
for the Hadd
offense of theft.
ÒAs for the
thief, whether
man or woman, cut his hand as punishment from God for what he
had done[1]Ó
A similar
problem in U.S.
Constitutional law is raised by the Second Amendment, [2]
which
holds that:
ÒA well
regulated Militia,
being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of
the people to
keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.Ó
Further,
the Fourteenth
Amendment holds (among other things) that:
ÒNo State
shall make or
enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or
immunities of citizens of
the United States;Ó
which is
interpreted[3]
as
imposing restrictions in the Bill of Rights on the states as
well as the
federal government.
In U.S.
Law, cities and
counties are considered creations of their state government,
so the
restrictions apply to them too. It appears to follow that any
law at any level
of U.S. Government prohibiting or restricting individual
ownership of
firearmsÑor, arguably, of tanks, fighter planes or nuclear
weaponsÑis unconstitutional.
In all
three cases,
authorities of the relevant legal systems have found ways of
working around the
fixed point created by the nominally authoritative rule. The
halakhic scholars
did it first. Thus Maimonides, basing his view on the work of
earlier
authorities, writes of the disobedient son:
He
is not
liable for stoning until he steals from his father and buys
meat and wine at a
cheap price. He must then eat it outside his father's domain,
together with a
group that are all empty and base. He must eat meat that is
raw, but not
entirely raw, cooked but not entirely cooked, as is the
practice of thieves. He
must drink the wine as it is thinned as the alcoholics drink.
He must eat a
quantity of meat weighing 50 dinarim in one sitting,
and drink half a log
of this wine at one time. É
É
According to the Oral Tradition, we learned that this law
concerns a youth of
thirteen between the time he grew two pubic hairs and the time
at which his
entire male organ is surrounded by pubic hair. After the
entire male organ is
surrounded by pubic hair, he is considered as independent and
is not executed
by stoning.
If
his
father desires to convict him and his mother does not desire,
or his mother
desires and his father does not desire, he is not judged as a
"wayward and
rebellious son," as implied by Deuteronomy 21:19: "His father
and
mother shall take hold of him."
If
one of
the parents has had his arm amputated, was lame, dumb, blind,
or deaf, the son
is not judged as a "wayward and rebellious son." These
concepts are
derived as follows: "His father and mother shall take hold of
him" -
This excludes parents with amputated arms" "And bring him out"
-
this excludes the lame. "They say" - this excludes the dumb.
"This son of ours" - This excludes the blind. "He does not
heed
our voice" - This excludes the dumb.[4]
It was a matter of debate
whether anyone had ever satisfied all the conditions and been
stoned.
Islamic
scholars followed a
similar, if less extreme, strategy. They held that for a
starving man to take
food was not theftÑand that anyone who stole perishable food
could be
presumed to have done it because he was starving, hence not
guilty of the Hadd
offense of theft. Taking property
that was unguarded did not count,[5]
so
stealing cattle only counted if they were stolen from a barn,
or at least from
near the owner's residence. Property in a house counted as
guarded only against
those who had not been invited to enter. The thing stolen must
be above some
minimal value, and the thief a competent adult. If the thief thought
the property was at
least partly hisÑwhether correctly or notÑit did not count as
theft,
so it could be argued that theft of public property never
counted, since all
Muslims were in some sense joint owners. Theft that failed to
meet one of these
requirements might still be punishable under tazir law but did not require the Hadd punishment of amputation.
In the
U.S., a variety of
arguments were used to limit the implications of the Second
AmendmentÑin
the view of some legal scholars, to essentially eliminate it.
The reference to
a militia could be interpreted as restricting the right to
members of the National
GuardÑprovided one was willing to ignore the broader sense of
unorganized
militia, consisting, when the Constitution was written, of all
adult males, and
also ignore the fact that the beginning of the Amendment
described a reason,
not a restriction. More plausibly, it could be argued that
since the purpose
was to maintain the militia, only weapons suitable for
military use counted. On
that basis, it was held that a law banning sawed off shotguns
did not violate
the amendment.[6]
As long as a majority of the members of the Supreme Court
favored restrictions
on firearm ownership, it was always possible to find some
basis for justifying
them.
A similar
issue arose during
the New Deal with the constitution's restraint on the power of
the federal
government. The tenth amendment reads:
ÒThe powers
not delegated to
the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited to it by
the States, are
reserved to the States respectively, or to the people.Ó
That
appears to make the
federal government one of enumerated powers, only allowed to
do those things
that the Constitution specifies. This raised a problem for an
administration
that wanted to do things
that did
not obviously fit into any of the enumerated categories, such
as imposing
restrictions on agricultural output in order to push up its
price. The solution
was found in the interstate commerce clause of the
Constitution, which holds
that: ÒThe Congress shall have Power É
To regulate Commerce ... among the several States É .Ó In Wickard v. Filburn, the government argued that a
farmer growing
crops to feed to his own livestock was Òsubstantially
involvedÓ in interstate
commerce, since if he had not grown those crops he would have
had to buy feed
for his animals, and such purchases would have affected the
price of feed on
the interstate market, hence that the activity could be
regulated by the
federal government. The Supreme Court, recently threatened
with packing if it
continued to block New Deal policies, accepted the argument.
Cases
sinceÑmost recently Gonzales
v. Raich,
which held that the interstate commerce clause justified a
federal ban on
marijuana produced and consumed within a single stateÑhave
very nearly
repealed the tenth amendment, since almost anything the
federal government
wants to do[7]
can be justified, to a sympathetic Supreme Court, as a
regulation of interstate
commerce.
These
examples demonstrate
the ability of legal scholars in three different legal systems
to find ways of
working around legal rules that they do not have the power to
change. In doing
so, they have employed a number of different tactics.
In each
case, the solution
depended on ÒinterpretingÓ the legal rule in a way that
converted it into
something closer to what the interpreters wanted. The process
begins with the
observation that no set of legal rules is sufficiently
complete to answer all
questions and eliminate all ambiguity, a point illustrated by
the failure of
the body of statutes of the Imperial Chinese system, very much
more extensive
and detailed than the rules of the Torah, the Koran, or the
Constitution, to do
so. It follows that someone must decide, when there are two
plausible readings
of the rule's implication, which to accept.
Once that
principle has been
accepted, the next step is to find some basis in the original
set of rules to
justify, not the particular interpretation, but the
unrestricted power to
interpret. In the case of Jewish law, the original
justification was twofold.
On the one hand, Torah explicitly commanded that, when the law
was unclear, the
opinion of the majority, interpreted as the majority of
halakhic scholars or,
more specifically, of the Sanhedrin, was to prevail.
One might
object that that
applied only when the law was unclear, and so could not trump
a command as
explicit as the one requiring a disobedient son to be stoned,
and surely could
not justify ÒinterpretationsÓ as far fetched as those used to
overrule that
command. One solution to that problem was the doctrine of the
oral Torah.[8]
The
interpretation of the halakhic scholars might seem
implausible, but it was
based on what God told Moses on Mount Sinai, passed down in
oral tradition to
the scholars of the present day, and so had the same
authoritative status as
the original rule.
Islamic
legal scholarship
followed an analogous pattern. The law was to be based not
only on the Koran
but on the practice (sunna)
of the
Prophet, as revealed in the traditions of what he and his
companions did and
said. Which traditions were to be trusted was a difficult
question, to be
resolved by scholarshipÑand the process could be biased in
favor of
traditions that supported the interpretations the scholars
wanted.[9]
Further,
one of the traditions held that the Muslims would never be
agreed on an
errorÑand by suitable interpretation of that, scholars got the
doctrine
of ijma, according
to which, once
there was a consensus in favor of an interpretation, the
matter was settled.
In U.S.
Constitutional
scholarship, the Supreme Court's power to interpret the
Constitution, even to
overrule Congress if it held that Congress was violating the
Constitution,
originated with Marbury
v. Madison, a
decision of the Supreme Court. It was made plausible by the
obvious need for
someone to interpret ambiguitiesÑand once established, could
be gradually
converted into the doctrine that, for legal purposes, the
Constitution was
whatever the Court said it was.
A second
solution to the
problem of working around rules that cannot be changed is to
impose the desired
rules through some mechanism to which the rules do not apply.
Thus halakhic scholars
defended the right of communal authorities in the diaspora to
do things
explicitly forbidden by Torah and/or previous rabbinic law on
the theory that
they had authority inherited from the kings of Israel, who had
enforced their
own law in a fashion clearly inconsistent with the constraints
of religious
law. Similarly, Islamic rulers created their own courts,
outside of the courts
that enforced Sharia, and used them to enforce rules
inconsistent with the
rules of Sharia, for example by convicting defendants without
the eyewitness
testimony of two Muslim witnesses, which Shari'a in most
contexts required. The
equivalent in U.S. Law is the use of the regulations of
executive agencies
to create the
equivalent of laws
without requiring congressional authorization.
So far I
have been focussing
on one problem created by divine legislationÑdealing with
cases where God
got it wrong, at least in the view of those interpreting and
enforcing the law.
A second problem is how to maintain judicial uniformity. What
happens if two
halakhic scholars, both judges, disagree about the
interpretation of Torah?
What they are disagreeing about
is not what the law should be but what it isÑand truth is not
determined
by majority vote. If each follows his interpretation, the
result is a legal
system where what outcome you get depends on which judge you
go to.
The
solution to that problem
is, arguably, the point of the story of the furnace of Akhnai.
The instruction
in the Torah to
deal with ambiguous
questions by accepting the view of the majority was
interpreted to mean that,
while the truth was not determined by majority vote, the law
was. A judge who
held to a minority interpretation after the Sanhedrin had
voted it down was
entitled to continue to argue for his position, but to judge
actual cases
according to it was a criminal offense. It was an offense that
led to Rabbi Eliezer
being banned, despite the strongest possible evidenceÑthe
literal voice
of GodÑthat his view was correct.
That
solution depended on
the existence of the Sanhedrin, or some other well defined
body of voters to
decide legal disputes. The Sanhedrin gave its last decision in
358 A.D.
Thereafter, legal uniformity depended on judges in the
diaspora agreeing about
what authorities they were willing to accept. The eventual
result was the
breakdown of legal uniformity, with different communities
accepting the doctrines
of different scholars, and with a good deal of law made by
local communal
authorities. The problem was ameliorated by the fact that most
legal
controversies were intra-communal, and so under a single set
of rules.
Islamic law
never had a
similar doctrine of majority rule, with the result that
differing
interpretations were allowed to coexist and, in the form of
the four orthodox
schools of Sunni law, still do. But the doctrine of consensus
at least provided
some basis for the claim that certain issues had been settled,
and so could not
be reopened.
In U.S.
Law, the authority
of the Supreme Court provides, at least in principle, a
solution to the
problem. As with the Jewish case, law need not, and often is
not, consistent
across states, or even across federal circuits, although, in
the latter case,
inconsistencies seen as problematic provide a basis for
Supreme Court review to
eliminate them.
As these
examples show, the
problems of divinely inspired law, and the solutions, are
similar across a
considerable range of societies and legal systems.
[1] There is some dispute as to the exact meaning of the words used, but this is the usual reading. Questioning the exact meaning of words is one of the tactics for working around such fixed points.
[2] The first ten amendments, commonly referred to as the bill of rights, were passed along with the original Constitution.
[3] There has been dispute as to how much of the Bill of Rights is incorporated. McDonald v. Chicago, 561 U.S. 3025, 130 S.Ct. 3020 (2010) was the first case in which the Supreme Court held that the Second Amendment was incorporated via the 14th Amendment, and so applied to state governments as well as to the federal government.
[4] This only a partial list of the conditions Maimonides states in Mishnah Torah, Mamrim 7:1-12.
[5] While this sounds odd, it corresponds to the rule in U.S. trade secret law that in order for information to qualify as a trade secret it must be protected. In both cases, protection arguably is needed to provide notice to the appropriator that the secret, or cow, is actually claimed as someoneÕs property.
[6] United States v. Miller, 307 U.S. 174 (1939)
[7] One exception
was United States
v. Lopez, which
held that the interstate
commerce clause was not a sufficient basis for a federal
law that made it
unlawful for any individual knowingly to possess a firearm
at a place that he
knew or had reasonable cause to believe was a school zone.
[8] 1 All the commandments that were given to Moshe at Sinai were given together with their interpretation, as it is written "and I will give thee the Tables of Stone, and the Law, and the Commandment" (Exodus 24,12). "Law" is the Written Law; and "Commandment" is its interpretation: We were commanded to fulfill the Law, according to the Commandment. And this Commandment is what is called the Oral Law.
2 The whole of the Law was written down by Moshe Our Teacher before he died, in his own hand. He gave a scroll of the Law to each tribe; and he put another scroll by the Ark for a witness, as it is written "take this book of the Law, and put it by the side of the Ark of the Covenant of the LORD your God, that it may be there for a witness against thee" (Deuteronomy 31,26).
3 But the Commandment, which is the interpretation of the Law--he did not write it down, but gave orders concerning it to the elders, to Yehoshua, and to all the rest of Israel, as it is written "all this word which I command you, that shall ye observe to do . . ." (Deuteronomy 13,1). For this reason, it is called the Oral Law.
(Maimonides, Mishnah Torah, Introduction)
[9] ÒIn nothing do we see learned men more prone to untruth than in the fabrication of Traditions.Ó Quoted in MohammedÕs People, p. 242.