The legal systems discussed in the past XXX chapters demonstrate some of the ways in which legal rules come into existence and change over time. In this chapter I will try to list all of them, and discuss the implications of each. As we will see, there is no simple one to one relation between legal systems and ways of creating law. The current U.S. Legal system is arguably created and changed in at least three different ways, Jewish and Muslim law in four.
Two of the legal systems we have
looked at are based, at least as understood by believers, on
divinely inspired commandmentsÑJewish law on the Torah,
Muslim law on the Koran. One problem raised by such a system
is eliminating the risk of legal inconsistency growing out
of inconsistent versions of the authoritative text.
In the case of the Koran, an
ÒofficialÓ text was established under 'Abd al Malik
(65/685-86/705) and all variant versions destroyed. We do
not know if a similar process occurred, at a much earlier
date, with regard to the written Torah, the Pentateuch.[1] The problem
was, however, raised by the oral Torah, instructions given
by God to Moses on Mount Sinai and passed down from him in a
chain of oral transmission; there was an obvious risk that
different legal scholars would differ on its content. This
was dealt with by the doctrine, based on the written Torah,
that in case of uncertainty one should go with the opinion
of the majority, interpreted as the majority of the
Sanhedrin.
A second problem with law based on
divine inspiration is that someone who can persuade others
that he is divinely inspired and so entitled to continue the
process can claim unlimited legal authority. The story of
the furnace of Akhnai, discussed in chapter XXX, can be read
as a strongly worded rejection of all such claims. Rabbi
Eleazar provides the strongest possible proof of divine
support, a string of miracles followed by a voice from the
heavens. Despite that, the sages reject his view of the
controversy; they tell God to butt out. Logically speaking
it makes little sense; even given that the majority get to
rule on what the law is, one would expect that after hearing
God's opinion on the subject the majority would change their
votes. But it makes perfect sense as a forceful rejection of
the claims of purported miracle workers to legal authority,
especially given the existence (in both Jewish and Islamic
history) of individuals who claimed miraculous powers and
supported their claims with (arguably fraudulent) miracles.[2]
The solution for Sunni law was the
doctrine that Mohammed was the final prophet, hence there
could be no further Koranic revelation. There were
occasional attempts by later figures to claim prophethood,
including in at least one case claimed authority for a new
Koran,[3] but they
were rejected by the bulk of the Islamic community. The Shia
Imams were claimed to have inherited in some form Mohammed's
authority, making their practice, like his, evidence of
God's will. That source of law ended when the final Imam[4] went into
occlusion, to reappear only in the final days.
A final problem is that God, like
the legislature, never answers all the questions that
matter. Hence divinely inspired law, like legislated law,
requires further interpretationÑand, in practice, there is
no sharp boundary between interpretation that fills gaps or
clarifies ambiguity in religious law and interpretation that
makes new law. In the Jewish case, interpretation occurred
first by vote of the Sanhedrin, influenced by the arguments
of scholars, and later as decisions and treatises by
scholars whose authority was based only on their reputation.
The opportunity for further interpretation was kept open by
the doctrine of hilkheta ke-vatra'ei,
Òthe law is in accordance with the views of the later
authorities.Ó[5] In the
Muslime case, on the other hand, the process of
interpretation was in theory ended in about the tenth
century by the shutting of the gates of ????, the end of
further deduction of law from Koran and hadith.
Cutting off further interpretation,
or at least novel interpretation, at some point, has both
advantages and disadvantages. Increased legal certainty and
reduction in costly efforts to change the law must be
balanced against a reduction in the ability to discover and
eliminate faults in the existing legal rules or to adapt law
to new circumstances. One might speculate that the decline
of Islamic civilization from its high point in about the
ninth century reflected in part consequences of the latter
problem.
Both Jewish and Islamic law, in
their original form, permitted a husband to divorce his wife
but did not permit the wife, even for cause, to divorce the
husband. Jewish law eventually changed to give the wife a de
facto, although not a
de jure,
mechanism of divorce: If she could persuade the court that
she had adequate cause, the court could compel the husband
to divorce her. Islamic law saw no such change.
Another example, one which
illustrates the potential for interpretation as a form of
legislation, is the decision of the rabbis of Israel early
in the 20th century to raise the legal age at
which a woman could marry. Their justification was the claim
that people were weaker now than they were when the Torah
was written, hence women were less able to bear children
young. The argument was obviously bogus, given the enormous
improvement in medicine, including obstetrics, over the
intervening millenia. But it permitted the rabbis to
eliminate a legal rule in Torah that they disapproved of[6] but had no
formal power to change, by interpreting it out of existence.
Another mechanism for producing
law, and the one that moderns are most familiar with, is
legislation by some authority entitled to make and change
law. In the case of Imperial Chinese law that authority was
the Emperor, in Athenian the assembly, in Jewish law first
rabbisÑwith their decision subject to approval by the
Sanhedrin while that body existedÑand later communal
authorities as well. In Amish law the legislationÑthe
content of the Ordnung of a congregationÑwas proposed
by the bishop, but required the unanimous approval of the
members of the congregation.
The oddest case, of those we have
looked at, is probably the Cheyenne. In at least some cases,
rules could apparently be made by declaration of a single
soldier society, following its resolution of a dispute, and
be seen as binding in the future on all Cheyenne. It is
unclear whether that ought to be viewed as a form of
legislation or as a mechanism for the development of
customary law.
Legislation has some obvious
advantages over the alternatives. There is in most cases a
well defined mechanism for changing the law, including
changes needed to clarify any ambiguity that comes up after
the initial legislation. In practice, however, legislation
never seems to be adequate by itself, not even in the
Chinese case, where the objective seems to have been to
create a complete mapping from offense to punishment. In
practice someone is always required to interpret the
application of the law to cases that do not perfectly fit
it. As in the case of religious law, the boundary between
resolving ambiguity and creating law is rarely a sharp
oneÑas illustrated by the expansion, in U.S. constitutional
law, of congressÕs authority to regulate interstate commerce
into something very close to a blank check to regulate all
economic activity.
Another approach to creating law is
binding precedent, as it exists in Anglo-American common
law. The courtÕs decision is considered binding on future
courts at or below its level. Thus interpretation determines
law not only for the particular case being interpreted but
for all future cases.
As compared to legislation, binding
precedent has several advantages. Since it grows out of the
resolution of a large number of cases, it makes possible a
more detailed set of legal rules than is likely to be
produced by either a single ruler or a legislature. Because
it originates with real cases, it is likely to map more
closely to real legal issues than a system of rules created
in the abstract. And because the rules it creates are
continually changing as new cases are resolved, with higher
courts free to overrule the precdents of lower and courts
able, if reluctantly, to overrule their own past precedents,
it creates a legal system that almost automatically adjusts
to changing circumstances.
A system of binding precedent has
disadvantages as well. It is being developed simultaneously
by multiple judges, often producing inconsistent rulings.
The inconsistency may eventually be resolved by a higher
court, but until it is, litigants will find that the outcome
of litigation depends on the choice of judge. In systems
where it is in the self-interest of judges to have cases
come to them, the result is to bias legal rules in favor of
whichever party controls the choice of forum.[7]
A further characteristics of such a
system, which some will see as a bug and some as a feature,
is its slow response time. Judges are likely to reach a high
level only late in their careers and, having reached that
level, remain there until forced to retire by old age or
death. A court of old judges is likely to interpret the law
in terms of views of the world popular when they were young.
Even if Legislatures are similarly staffed, in a democratic
system aging legislators are under pressure to support
positions popular with the current electorate.
For a very different approach,
consider Somali law as described by Van Notten or
pre-Islamic bedouin law as described by Schacht. In both
systems, judges are arbitrators; their judgements are seen
as opinions about the law, not decisions creating it. There
is precedent, but of a very different sort than in systems
where precedent is binding. The fact that multiple
arbitrators saw the customary law as implying a particular
resolution to some legal issue is evidence that it does
imply that resolution, especially if other people regarded
the verdicts produced as just and if those who produced them
continue to be chosen as arbitrators. Past decisions
influence future decisions, but as evidence not binding
precedent.
To see the same pattern in modern
common law, consider the case of Annie Lee Turner et al.
v. Big Lake Oil Company et al. The Supreme Court of Texas had
to determine what compensation, if any, Big Lake Oil
Company owed Annie Lee Turner and her neighbors for damage
done to their property by the escape of polluted water
from Big LakeÕs storage pools. A key issue was whether Big
Lake is liable only if it was negligent or whether it is strictly
liable for any damage done.
The Texas judges looked first not
to the statute law of Texas but to a case decided in another
country in another century: Rylands v Fletcher, decided by a committee of the
British House of Lords in 1868. They spent a considerable
part of the written opinion explaining why it reached a
different result, despite the fact that the House of Lords
had never had any authority over the law of Texas.
The law lords who decided Rylands
v Fletcher were a
court deciding the outcome of a particular case, but they
were also an expert body interpreting the common law of
England. In that second role the conclusion they reached
was relevant to, although not determinative of, the
deliberations of a Texas court deciding a similar case
based on the same underlying system of law. An English
judge has authority over an American case in precisely the
same sense in which an English scholar has authority over
a dispute in his field carried on by American scholars; he
is an expert whose opinion is relevant to deciding a
disputed question of fact.
Seen from this point of view, the
common law is a system both
of binding precedent and informative precedent.
For another example of a mixed
system, consider Amish law. The final decision that
determines the content of a congregationÕs ordnung is legislation, albeit of a
somwhat odd sort. But the process that changes ordnung looks more like the process by
which customary law is changed. Someone does something
that is arguably in violation of the current ordnung, or at least of the ordnung as currently interpreted. If
others object, then the next time agreement must be
reached the congregation will probably find that what he
did is forbiddenÑand he may have to publicly confess to a
misdeed. But if few or none object and some others imitate
him, the view of what is or is not permitted may change,
and the changed view be explicitly incorporated in the
next redefinition of the rules.
Yet another example is Jewish law
in the diaspora. It was ultimately based on divine
revelation. It incorporated extensive legislation, first by
the rabbis and later by communal authorities as well, as
well as interpretation by halakhic authorities over an
extended period of time, producing treatises on the law such
as the Mishah Torah of Maimonides.
Such treatises claimed not to
create law but to discover and describe it. The local
halakhic authorities were offering their interpretation of
an existing body of customary law. The claim of Maimonides
and others was not that their opinions were a binding
precedentÑthat would be inconsistent with both the rule that
the law was according to the opinion of the later
authorities and the actual practice of legal scholars, often
functioning as judges, of basing their decisions on the
opinions of past legal scholars as far back as they were
available. One of the chief criticisms of MaimonidesÕ work
was that, because to each legal question he gave only one
answer, he failed to provide a judge with the information,
the varying opinions and arguments of past scholars, needed
to reach a conclusion.
Customary law is a nebulous
concept, hard to get a grip on. We know where legislated law
comes from, where judge made law in a system of binding
precedent comes from, where law based on divine revelation
comes from. It is much less clear who creates customary law,
when, or how. As a justice famously said of pornography, you
know it when you see it.
It may help to consider the
particular form of customary law with which we are all
familiar, because we are all embedded in it. For example:
Before going to class yesterday I
went in search of a clean pair of pants, the previous pair
having just gone into the washing machine. Hanging in my
closet was a worn pair of blue jeans. They
would probably have been more comfortable, perhaps also
warmer, than the the available slacks, yet I
gave no serious thought to wearing themÑbecause doing so
would have violated social norms for professors teaching
courses.
Such norms are a form of customary law, one that maintains
itself without the aid of judges or arbitrators. We all have
at least a rough idea of what patterns of behavior are or
are not acceptable in our society. Nobody legislated those
rules, nobody legislates their changes, yet they exist and,
over time, change. The mechanism is much the same as among
the Amish. A particularly brave and self-assured professor
chooses to push the boundaries, to appear before his class
in shorts and flip flopsÑI have a real example in mind. If
students and colleagues look at him oddly, if he notes that
at the next faculty meeting his opinions carry less weight
than in the past, if his wife mentions that a colleagueÕs
wife asked her if her husband was going through some sort of
stage, he may abandon his norm-violating behavior. If nobody
seems particularly shocked, if colleagues react, if at all,
with friendly amusement, he continues it. After a whileÑa
week, a month, perhaps a yearÑanother professor shows up in
shorts, perhaps after discovering at the last minute that
all his pants either are in the wash or should be. The norm
changes.
Social norms are customary law with
which all of us have first hand experience. They are also,
arguably, the source of all other customary law. Individuals
behave in a certain way, constrained by the expectations of
others and the social consequences when others approve or
disapprove of their acts. When a dispute arises, presenting
the risk of violence between the parties and the more
attractive alternative of an arbitrated decision, it seems
plausible that the arbitrator will rule on the basis of what
behavior is or is not accepted in that society. Thus norms,
enforced for the most part by social pressure, evolve into
customary law enforceable by violence or the threat of
violence.
In discussing different ways of
making law I have so far ignored the most important question
of allÑwhat sort of law they will make. To what extent can
we expect one or another of these mechanisms to produce good
law, law that promotes the welfare of those to whom it
applies?[8]
I have ignored the question
because, for the most part, I cannot answer it. If divinely
inspired law really is inspired by a benevolent deity, the
result should be good law; but I have my doubts. Similarly
if legislated law is created by a wise and benevolent ruler,
but I know of no reason to expect that either.
Some might argue that legislated
law produced by an elected legislature will be designed in
the interest of the voters, since otherwise the legislators
will be voted out of power, but I find that claim
unconvincing. The body of economics known as public choice
theory provides persuasive arguments against that particular
form of polyannism. Individual voters, if rational, realize
that their vote has little effect on political outcomes, so
devote little effort to gathering the information needed to
make correct decisions. Politicians rarely help out by
labeling themselves as bad guys, or even by labeling their
legislation as a bill to make farmers richer and city folk
poorerÑalthough that is a reasonable description of quite a
lot of legislation passed by the U.S. congress in my
lifetime. The result, as I have argued elsewhere, is a
system that frequently produces bad law, a theoretical
conclusion for which I find quite a lot of empirical
support.
Consider the case of foreign trade.[9] Economists
have known for about two hundred years that a country that
imposes tariffs on imports will under most circumstances
make its inhabitant worse off by doing so, although there
are some possible exceptions. For that entire period, most
countries have chosen to impose tariffs, and done so in a
way strikingly inconsistent with the theoretical arguments
for why a tariff might occasionally be a good idea;
protection is provided not to infant industries but to
senile industries. The arguments offered for imposing those
tariffs hinge not on imperfections in the conventional
economic analysis but on ignorance of it; they are the same
arguments that were refuted two hundred years ago. It is
hard to square those observations with a model in which
legislators find it necessary to pass good law in order to
stay in office.
What about judge made law? Richard
Posner argued, long ago, that common law tends to be
economic efficient, supporting that argument with economic
analysis of the efficiency of common law rules. In my view,
neither the evidence he offers nor the theoretical argument
offered by him and others is sufficient to establish the
truth of that claim; interested readers will find the
question discussed at length in my LawÕs Order.[10]
Which leaves us with customary law.
Consider a norm which, if adopted
by a group of individuals for interactions among its
members, makes them better offÑsay a norm of honest dealing.
Once one group has adopted it, one would expect others to
observe the result and either join that group or imitate it.
Thus desirable norms could spread through a society. Once
established, they could become the basis out of which
customary law develops.
There is an important limitation to this argument; to see it, consider the norms that applied to whalers in the 19th century. In Order Without Law, Robert Ellickson persuasively argued that the whalers had an efficient set of norms with regard to issues such as what happened when one ship initially harpooned a whale and another eventually killed it, norms that efficiently changed as the whalers shifted from hunting one species of whale to another.
The reason that they shifted their
prey was that one species after another was being hunted to
near-extinction. That suggests that they would have been
better off with a norm that restricted the number of whales
killed to a number that would not seriously reduce the
population. No such norm existed.
The reason should be obvious. A
norm of restricted whaling benefits all whalers if they all
follow it. But the benefit from my restraint goes to other
whalers whether or not they act similarly. The right rule
for all is to restrict. The right rule for any individual,
or any group much smaller than all whalers, is to free ride
on the restrictions of others. The problem is strictly
analogous to the familiar case of the prisonerÕs dilemma or,
more generally, to what economists refer to as market
failure,[11] a situation
where individual rationality does not lead to group
rationality.
It follows that customary law based
on social norms ought to do a good job of generating the
first sort of rules, rules which benefit the members of any
group that adopts them. But there is no reason to expect it
to do a similarly good job of generating rules of the second
sort, rules which it is in the interest of all of us for all
of us to follow but not in the interest of any individual to
himself follow.
I have described one mechanism that
has some tendency to generate good law, within limits. A
second mechanism applies to the specific case of contract
law. After I have signed a contract with you, I would prefer
law that favors me in any resulting dispute. But before we
have signed the contract, we have a common interest in law
that maximizes our combined benefitÑbecause the expected
cost to you of any rule that favors me will reduce the price
you are willing to pay me for whatever I am contributing to
our joint project or increase the price you will charge for
whatever you are contributing. Only if the benefit to me is
larger than the cost to you will it be in my interest to
insist on the rule.
Which implies that a legal system in which individuals choose in advance the judge, arbitrator, or court that will interpret their contract will tend to produce good law, at least from the standpoint of the contracting parties.
[1] A similar process has occurred in Judaism much more recently, in part due to the discovery of the Dead Sea scrolls. [add details when found]
[2] Reference to Islamic controversial miracle worker. Jewish as well?
[3] Reference to ÒBerber KoranÓ etc.
[4] Who the final Imam was and when is one of the issues on which different Shia sects differ.
[5] Jephthah in his generation has as much authority as Samuel in his generation." This doctrine is in tension with the idea that, in determining what the law was, a scholar should give greater weight to the views of earlier authorities, and was and is not universally accepted.
[6] Perhaps because sephardic Jews from the Middle East and North Africa were marrying off their daughters at twelve, as Jewish law permitted them to do, in violation of contemporary European norms.
[7] Article by Mark Klerman on the effect of court competition on English common law.
[8] In the context of the economic analysis of law, this is usually put in terms of economically efficient, or Òwealth maximizing,Ó law. For the purposes of this book I prefer to be deliberately vaguer than that.
[9] For a much more detailed analysis of these issues see my Price Theory; the relevant chapter is webbed at: http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/Price_Theory/PThy_Chapter_19/PThy_Chap_19.html
[10] Webbed at
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Laws_Order_draft/laws_order_ToC.htm.
[11] Add reference to something of mine expanding on this, preferably webbed.