Commanche, Kiowa and Cheyenne: The Plains Indians

Moderns are inclined to view more primitive societies as following the same pattern of life for century after century. If, after all, they were capable of change, surely they would have progressed, become more like us, ceased to be primitive. The plains indians provide a striking counterexample. Their immemorial life style was in fact a brand new invention when white men first came into substantial contact with them.

The reason it was a new invention is that hunting buffalo from horseback requires horses. There were no horses in America until the Spanish brought them and none available to North American indians until enough time had passed for horses that had escaped the Spanish to multiply in the wild and spread north.

Faced with a sudden opportunity for progress, the chance to stop scratching in the earth as primitive agriculturalists and turn into noble savages hunting buffalo, living in tipis, and proving their manhood by making war on each other, the indian tribes living on or near the great plains seized the opportunity. The result was the development, in the 18th century, of a common material culture shared by a variety of tribes with quite different origins. It depended on the horse, but also made good use of the rifle, rifles having been initially provided by the English to tribes willing to fight tribes allied with the French, and by the French to tribes willing to fight those allied with the English.

In this chapter I will discuss what is known about the legal systems of three tribes. My discussion is based mainly on a chapter by Hoebel,[1] covering all three tribes, and a book by Llewellyn and Hoebel,[2] covering the Cheyenne in much greater detail.

 

Commanche

ÒOnce there were a bunch of Commanche out looking for troubleÓ

(The usual start of an account by a Commanche informant, according to Hoebel)

I start with the Commanche; their government is the simplest of the three to describe, since they didnÕt have one. A Commanche war chief was simply an entrepreneur, a warrior who announced his intent to go steal horses from the Mexicans, Americans, or some other tribe, and invited anyone interested to come along. Within the war party he had absolute rule, but anyone unhappy with the situation was free to leave. Along similar lines, the Commanche peace chief was simply an individual who others were willing to follow. If he chose to go one direction and the rest of the band another, he was no longer a peace chief.

The Commanche, in other words, were anarchists, their social system allowing for nothing recognizable as a government. One of the problems that concerns modern anarchists is how to defend their society against adjacent states, given the difficulty of raising and funding an army without a draft, taxation, feudal obligations, or something along similar lines.[3]

The Commanche reversed the situation, raising the problem of defending adjacent states, and anyone else in the neighborhood, from them. They drove the Apache from the southern plains, raided the Mexicans for horses and slaves, and, despite the disadvantage of lower technology and smaller population, blocked American expansion across Texas for decades, fairly earning the title of Spartans of the plains. Facing an overwhelmingly superior enemy they were eventually defeated, but only after making a very impressive fight of it.

Part of the reason, seen from an economistÕs perspective, is that they made warfare into a private rather than a public good. For most of their history, the incentive to fight was not the welfare of the tribe but of the individual warrior. Successful raids produced valuable loot. Heroic and successful fighting produced status.

One way of getting status was to steal horses from outsiders. Another was to face down another Commanche warrior. The excuse for doing so was provided by the common practice of wife stealing.

The strongest bond within the tribe was between brothers who, among other things, shared their wives and had the power to marry off their sisters. From the standpoint of the brother, the ideal brother-in-law was a wealthy and successful warrior. The sister, however, might prefer someone earlier in his career, younger and more handsomeÑand, given the opportunity, leave the husband chosen for her by her brothers to run away with one such. The incentive of the wife-stealer was less possession of the wife than the opportunity to outface the husband.

Wife stealing was illegal and done openly, so guilt was not an issue. Compensation was. The husband was expected to confront the wife stealer and demand generous compensation, with the amount an increasing function of the wealth of the stealer and the prowess of the husband, a decreasing function of the prowess of the stealer. There being no government to enforce the law, the threat that backed the demand was the private use of force. Pay or IÕll kill you.

Carrying out that threat was neither desired nor likely, since if the husband killed the stealer (or vice versa) the victimÕs kin would take revenge by killing the killer. The intended result of the threat was to set off the game that economists call Òbilateral monopoly,Ó a bargaining game in which the parties have a common interest in a peaceful resolution of their dispute but a conflict over the terms, in this case over how much will be given in compensation to the wronged husband.

What if the stealer was clearly the more dangerous man of the twoÑnot unlikely, since a prudent man in search of status would prefer not to steal from too able a husband? The husband had the option of calling in his brothers or other kin to support his threats. The stealer, having set off the conflict in order to prove his status, had no such optionÑasking for help would be to admit that he had bitten off more than he could chew, and besides, he was on what everyone saw as the wrong side of the (unwritten) law. So at that point the stealer backs down and agrees to pay substantial damages, which damages are collected not by the husband but by his helpers.

Suppose the husband had no brothers? His option then was to find a champion, a brave, generous, well thought of warrior willing to take over the case and face down the stealer. This time the damage payment went to the husband. The championÕs payment was the status gained by his willingness to risk himself in defense of the right and his success in forcing another warrior to back down. Much the same pattern appears in some of the Icelandic sagas, where a bully who relies too heavily on his and his friendsÕ strength to let him violate the rights of weaker men is brought down by someone still more formidable out to establish his own status.[4]

Wife stealing cases seem to have been the nearest thing to legal disputes among the Commanche. So far as conflicts between husband and wife, most likely to occur when the husband suspected his wife of adultery, the husband had pretty much a free hand, up to and including torturing his wife to make her name her lover or killing her. One possible resolution was for the wife to swear by earth and sky that she was innocent, at which point the husband accepted the oathÑin the belief that if she is lying, then earth and sky would eventually kill her. As far as minor theft was concerned, the Commanche, like the other two tribes I will discuss, regarded such matters as beneath the notice of a warrior. As a Cheyenne would have put it, Òif you had asked, I would have given it to you.Ó

That attitude, as well as other features of plains indian behavior that I will be discussing in the context of the Cheyenne, suggests one important feature of those societiesÑin their own terms, they were wealthy. Men frequently had more horses than they themselves had use for, and so were free to use the surplus to prove their generosity by giving some away. In an uncertain environment, they were from time to time at risk of starving to death during the winter. But the most important form of portable, indeed self-portable on four legs, wealth was plentiful.

What about murder? Among the Commanche, as already mentioned, a first killing required a second, of the killer by the kin of his victim. At that point the matter ended. The second killing was justified by the first, and so required no further vengeance. For these purposes, killing a favorite horse, thought of as having a soul, counted as murder and so justified the killing (of the human responsible) in revenge.

An exception to the rule of a life for a life occurred in the context of sorcery. Every Commanche male was expected at some point to go on a vision quest and end up with some sort of magical power, typically restricted by a tabu whose violation could cost his life. For the most part such power was used for the good of the tribe and the individual, but there were Òmean medicine men,Ó individuals with a greater than usual share of magical power and an inclination to misuse it, sometimes lethally.

The first recourse, if someone was believed to be dying from sorcery, was to get a good medicine man to cure him. If that failed, the next step was to confront the sorcerer believed responsible and try to get him to stop what he was doing. If that failed, however, there was no obligation to kill the sorcerer, possibly because doing so was seen as too dangerous, possibly because in that case, unlike an ordinary murder followed by revenge, there might be a serious risk of blaming the wrong man.

What if it was believed that a particular bad medicine man was responsible for multiple deaths? At that point, the Commanche make use of the nearest thing their society has to criminal law. The rest of the tribe meets together, concludes that the guilty individual must die, and either kills him or tricks him into violating his own tabu and so dying.

 

The Kiowa

The Kiowa, while in some ways similar to the Commanche, had something a little closer to a government and much closer to a well defined class/rank system. The latter consisted of four classes. The Onde were the high status warriors, sufficiently high that they had no need to further demonstrate their courage or prowess; they are estimated to have been at most ten percent of the men. The Ondegupta were the would-be Onde, the pushy up and coming warriors trying to establish their claim to the top category. Not surprisingly, the Ondegupta were the chief source of conflict within the tribe as they, like their Commanche equivalent, tried to gain status. Below them were the common men, and below those the Dapom, the dregs of society, functioning as hangers-on of the more important Kiowa and tolerated petty thieves.

Kiowa bands had recognized headmen, almost all of Onde rank, who in practice made important decisions for the band. Kiowa war chiefs, like Commanche war chiefs, were the leaders of war parties.

In addition to these, there were ten keepers of medicine bundles, tribal fetishes with magical power, and one keeper of the Sun Dance fetish, as such the nominal grand chief of the tribe, all of whom played an important role in settling disputes. An Ondegupta who claimed to have been wronged by another made a great show of threatening a violent response, while letting himself be restrained by the bystanders from actually doing anything until one of the ten medicine bundle bearers showed up with his pipe, asking him to accept a peaceful settlement with suitable compensation. Usually the offer was accepted. If not, a second medicine bundle bearer would apper and, if necessary, a third and a fourth. It was believed that refusal of the fourth meant death by supernatural agency.

Both men were trying to demonstrate their courage and determination, with the risk that the bluff might became reality. If someone was killed, he might be killed in retaliation by his victimÕs kin or they might accept compensation, the equivalent to the Icelandic wergeld or the blood money that atoned for killing under Sharia or among the Somali. The man who had killed was believed to become unlucky as a result, like a murderer did in ancient Athens, but his presence did not, as with the Cheyenne to be discussed below, polute the tribe.

In addition to the keepers of the medicine bundles, the Kiowa had military fraternities, roughly similar to those of the Cheyenne.

 

The Cheyenne

 

Of the three tribes, perhaps of all the plains indians, the Cheyenne came closest to having a governmentÑpart of the year. The usual pattern was that the entire tribe, possibly as many as four thousand of them, gathered together in a single camp in summer when food was plentiful, in particular in the form of buffalo to be hunted. During the winter the tribe separated into much smaller bands and dispersed in search of game.

The summer encampment was the site of the council of forty four, the government, or perhaps nascent government, of the tribe. It was a self-perpetuating body; how the original members were chosen does not seem to be known. Every tenth year, the council was renewed. Each existing member chose a successor, usually from his own band but not his own son. A chief could not succeed himself, but he could be kept in the council if another chief was willing to name him as his successor.

There were four priest chiefs among the forty-four, each associated with a supernatural power, plus one keeper of the sweet-medicine, the most important of the tribal fetishes. When the council was renewed, each priest chief chose his successor from among the retiring chiefs of the council. If a priest chief died, his successor was chosen by the others.

In addition to the Council, there wer also soldier societies, military fraternities, existing initially as social groups, but over time taking on some governmental responsibilities. One of the societies, the dog soldiers, constituted its own band, and so existed as a single unit through the entire year. Each of the others had members dispersed among the bands, and so was together only during the summer encampment. Each of the soldier societies had two chiefs, functioning as war chiefs, and two Òservants,Ó lower level chiefs responsible for providing a particularly dangerous part of the defense against attackers.

The council was responsible for making decisions about war or peace with other tribes, for deciding cases of homicide or whether to permit the readmission of an exiled killer, and deciding the movements of the tribe in search of game. The impression from incidents described in some detail by Hoebel and Llewellyn is that, in practice, it was a consensus process. One chief might decide that the tribe should move in some direction. He would take council with several others, they would eventually call together all of the council chiefs, confer, and have the conclusion announced to the tribe. In some other contexts, such as deciding on a peace treaty with another tribe, the process would involve a good deal of back and forth between the Council and one or more of the soldier societies. The Council had the right to make the decision, but in practice it had to be made in consultation with others, most obviously the others who would actually implement it.

One further responsibility of the Council was to control the buffalo hunt, a mass effort by the entire tribe, conducted under the authority of one of the soldier societies selected for the purpose. The basic rule was that nobody was to attack a buffalo until the word was given, at which point the line of hunters would charge the herd, with the ends of the line wrapping around to entirely enclose it.

It is unclear from the accounts to what degree this was a practical policy designed to kill buffalo as effectively as possible, and to what degree a ceremonial hunt designed to establish the authority of tribal rules, in this case the rule against premature hunting. In practice, the rule was not uncommonly violated, perhaps typically by young warriors out to prove that they could get away with it.

The following account is from one of the informants quoted by Hoebel and Llewellyn:

All the hunters went out in a line with the Shield Soldiers in front to hold them back. Just as they were coming up over a long ridge down wind from where the scouts had reported the herd they saw two men down in the valley riding in among the buffalo. A Shield Soldier chief gave the signal to his men. They paid no attention to the buffalo, but charged in a long line on the two violators of the rules. Little Old Man shouted out for everyone to whip them: ÒThose who fail or hesitate shall get a good beating themselves.Ó

The first men to reach the spot shot and killed the horses from under the hunters. As each soldier reached the miscreants he slashed them with his riding whip. Then some seized the guns of the two and smashed them.

When the punishment was done, the father of these two boys rode up. It was Two Forks, a member of the Dakota tribe, who had been living with the Cheyennes for some time. He looked at his sons beforee talking. ÒNow you have done wrong. You failed to obey the law of this tribe. You went out alone and you did not give the other people a chance. This is what has happened to you.Ó

Then the Shield Soldier chiefs took up the talk. ÒNow you know what we do when anyone disobeys our ourders,Ó they declared. ÒNow you know we mean what we say.Ó The boys did not say anything.

After that the chiefs relented. This was not alone because of the fact that the culprits were Dakotas. They called their men to gather around. ÒLook how these two boys are here in our midst. Now they have no horses and no weapons. What do you men want to do about it?Ó

One of the soliders spoke up. ÒWell, I have some extra horses. I will give one of them to them.Ó Then another soldier did the same thing.

Bear Standing On a Ridge was the third to speak out. ÒWell,Ó he announced, Òwe broke those guns they had. I have two guns. I will give them one.Ó

All the others said, ÒIpewa, good.Ó

The account has several interesting features, consistent with other such accounts. To begin with, the punishment of offenders consisted of whipping them and destroying their property. On the face of it, the latter seems a wasteful form of punishment. Why not replace the destruction by a fine, seizing the property and using it for the good of the tribe, or perhaps the soldier society that, in this case, was enforcing the rules.

One possible answer is that making punishment profitable invites excessive or unwarranted punishment[5]Ñthe same problem that Athenian law attempted to solve by combining a profitable punishment via private prosecution, a share of the fine, with a penalty for unsuccessful prosecution. It might be a particularly serious risk in a system as unstructured as the Cheyenne. Hunting too early violated a well understood rule, but exactly what the consequences were, in that case and most others, was up to the particular people, often the members of one of the soldier societies, who detected the offense and punished the offender. Customs that permit the enforcers to shoot horses but not to confiscate them are one way of eliminating the risk.

The second interesting, and to us odd, feature of the story is the replacement of the killed horses and destroyed gun by the enforcers. By not trying to evade capture, offer arguments in their defense, or resist the destruction of their property, the two boys were implicitly conceding the authority of the tribal rule they had violated and of the enforcers of that rule. Once they had done that they were, in effect, readmitted to respectabilityÑand since young men obviously couldnÕt be left on the prairie, just before the hunt started, without horses or guns, horses and at least one gun were generously donated by members of the same group that had imposed the punishment.

In this case the Shield Soldiers were acting to enforce the existing rule against premature hunting, having been appointed to that task by the Council of forty-four, although the details of the enforcement were of their own invention. In addition to monitoring the actual hunt, the members of the selected soldier societies could also investigate charges of premature hunting, by insisting on searching the tipi of the accused. If fresh buffalo meat was found, a likely punishment (as for some other offenses) was to destroy the tipi.

 

In other cases described by the informants, members of the soldier societies acted to enforce other rules, in some cases engaging in de facto legislation, solving a particular problem and proclaiming a general rule to cover such situations in the future. Thus, for example:

ÒWhile Wolf Lies Down was away, a friend took one of his horses to ride to war. This man had brought his bow and arrow and left them in the lodge of the horseÕs owner. When Wolf Lies Down returned, he knew by this token security who had his horse, so he said nothing.

A year passed without the horseÕs return, and then Wolf lies down invited the Elk Soldier chiefs to his lodge, because he was in their society. [He asks what he should do. The chiefs agree to send someone to bring back the borrower or word from him. Eventually the messenger returns with the borrower, leading two horses. He confirms that he borrowed the history, but was gone longer than he planned to be, and offers to both return the horse he borrowed and give Wolf Lies Down two other horses and his bow and arrow. ]

Then up spoke Wolf Lies Down. ÒI am glad to hear my friend say these things. Now I feel better. I shall take one of those horses, but I am giving him that one he borrowed to keep. From now on we shall be bosom friends.Ó

The chiefs declared É.

ÒNow we shall make a new rule. There shall be no more borrowing of horses without asking. If any man takes anotherÕs goods without asking, we will go over and get them back for him. More than that, if the taker tries to keep them, we will give him a whipping.Ó

 

When the tribe was broken up into separate bands, neither the council nor the full soldier societies (except for the dog soldiers, who were their own band) was available to deal with matters. Council chiefs functioned as peace chiefs in their individual bands, leaders although with imprecisely defined powers, and to some degree members of the soldier societies acted to enforce group decisions, for instance by preventing a minority of the band who disagreed with a decision on which way to go from openly splitting off. At all times, the Council chiefs were expected to be exemplars of moderation and good behavior, even when wronged, and paragons of generosity. A Cheyenne who did not think he could live up to the standard expected of a council chief might decline the office on that account. As Sun Road put it:

ÒWhen a dog is running after a bitch in heatÑif my wife is chased by another man, I might weaken and open my mouth. Then it would be well if another had the medicine and not I.Ó

In a warrior society where it is common for semi-official enforcers to punish those they regard as rules violators by whipping them or shooting their horses, there is an obvious risk that someone will go too far, and either enforcer or enforcee end up dead. The Cheyenne has a simple and elegant solution to that problem. Beating up another Cheyenne was between you and him. Killing another Cheyenne, for any reason, meant exile from the tribe.

The reason, as they saw it, was not punishment but hygiene. Killing a fellow Cheyenne polluted the medicine arrows that were one of the tribal fetishes; blood would mysteriously appear on their feathers. It also polluted the killer; he smelled of death, and the pollution was contagious. Until the arrows had been ceremonially renewed and the killer exiled, no luck could be expected in hunting or warfare.

Exile was not lethal; there were other friendly tribes on the plains. After a period of some years the exiled man could petition to be readmitted to the tribe, possibly bringing with him a horse loaded with tobacco to demonstrate his repentance. If the kin of his victim were willing he might be readmitted, subject to conditions that they imposed. But for the rest of his life, nobody would share his pipe or eat from his bowl. The smell of death might be weakened enough by time to permit his presence in the tribe, but it was still contagious.

As in Athens.



[1] E. Adamson Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man, Harvard University Press, 1967.

[2] K.N. Llewellyn and E. Adamson Hoebel, The Cheyenne Way, U of Oklahoma Press 1941.

[3] For one discussion of the problem, see D. Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom, Chapter XXX.

[4] Find and cite the case IÕm thinking of.

[5] For a discussion of the same issue in a modern context, see D. Friedman, "Reflections on Optimal Punishment or Should the Rich Pay Higher Fines?," Research in Law and Economics, (1981)