Review of Murder at the Margin, by
Marshall Jevons. Glen Ridge, New Jersey: Thomas Horton and Daughters, 1978, 168 pages.
Public Choice, 1979,
Vol. 34, No. 2 (1979), pp. 233-236
In Murder
at the Margin, Marshall Jevons tries to do for economics what G. K. Chesterton did for Catholicism in
the
Father Brown stories
and Harry Kemelman is currently doing for Judaism in Friday the Rabbi Slept Late and other days of the week. A detective mystery may seem a strange vehicle for explaining and defending
a world view, religious or otherwise,· but it is, after all, a microcosm of the application of human wisdom
to the understanding of human behavior.
Any system of thought that claims to explain
the what and why of everything should have an easy time deducing who put the poison in the soup.
This
is especially true of economics, which,
thanks to the work of such 'economic
imperialists' as Gary Becker and Gordon Tullock,
no longer defines itself as the study of the allocation of limited resources
to diverse ends, but as the science
of understanding human behavior on the assumption that individuals rationally pursue ends, that, in Von Mises' words, 'human action is purposive behavior'.
Criminal behavior in particular has been
analyzed in this way by Becker, Landes,
and others. One might hope that
an economic detective story could not only introduce
economics, a notoriously unpalatable
subject, to noneconomists in an entertaining fashion, but at the same time make plausible its claim to be the new master science, the organizing principle
around which any scientific understanding
of human behavior must be built.
This is a difficult
task, and unfortunately Murder at the Margin does not accomplish it. It fails at two levels. Considered simply as a detective story it is not
a very good one; although
the writing is often
entertaining, the characters are superficial and the author relies heavily on telling
instead of showing.
The denouement depends on an economic theorem
which few
readers will either know in
advance or correctly understand after the author has explained
it; it thus violates one of the central rules of the genre, that a sufficiently clever reader should
be able to figure out the solution
for him self. This is even worse for a mystery whose detective
is an economist than it would be if he were a chemist or engineer using some technical
trick to identify the murderer;
one of the beauties of economics is that understanding it depends more on clear thinking and less on rote knowledge
than with almost any other science.
As a mystery, the book is neither much better nor much worse than one would expect for a first book by an unknown author.
As an explanation
of economics, it is much worse than one would expect from an author with two such distinguished names. The hero, Professor Spearman, is a Nobel
Prize-winning economist; the author goes out
of his way to tell us how brilliant he is, and
how fascinated with his own discipline. Spearman
is continually noting and commenting on the economic behavior of those around him; the author
uses these comments
to give the reader brief lessons in economics. It is undoubtedly true that some great economists find it interesting to apply
economic analysis to the world immediately around them, but one of the things that distinguishes great economists from other people is that the resulting
observations are nontrivial ones. Professor Spearman's applications of economics are, with only a few exceptions,
observations that when prices fall demand increases. Perhaps
this is all the economics which mystery readers
can absorb, although
I doubt it, but as a
portrait of an economist it is about as satisfactory as if a great mathematician was shown continually adding up columns
of numbers while pointing out with delight
that the sum was the same whatever
order you added them in.
Of Professor Spearman's two nontrivial applications of economics
one is the crucial deduction
by which the murder is solved; since the laws that govern
the reviewing of detective stories
forbid giving away the solution,
I will simply say that I believe
the theorem the author applies
is inapplicable to the particular problem to which he applies
it. The other exception involves a 'Prisoner's Dilemma'. Professor Spearman
describes this as involving a minimax
solution, and says 'the safest strategy is for him to plead
guilty, figuring his partner will do the same and against the chance
that his partner might even plead innocent'. This, of course, is wrong; minimax or saddle point is the solution concept
appropriate to two-person fixed-sum games, of which Prisoner's Dilemma is not one, and one of the things
that makes the Prisoner's Dilemma seem so paradoxical is that the decision of one prisoner
to confess does not depend on his gambling that his partner will also confess;
as long as the two men's actions are independent,
confession dominates refusing to confess whatever the other prisoner
chooses to do.
More serious
than such technical mistakes
is the methodological error that underlies all of Professor
Spearman's detective efforts — his misapplication of the rationality axiom. Rationality involves two assumptions. The first is that individuals choose the best possible means to their ends. Taken by
itself, this has no predictive content; whatever the individual does can
be explained by assuming that doing that particular thing - buying a good
at a
higher price than necessary, for example - is itself the end sought.
One must therefore add a second assumption
limiting ends. While hard to define exactly, this amounts to assuming that utility functions are reasonably
simple - at least simple enough
so that if all of the obvious ends one might seek are best served by buying a good at the
lowest possible price, one's utility function will not have been specially tailored for the perverse purpose of refuting that conclusion.
What makes this assumption useful is not that it is always true.
There may well be individuals - those, for instance, who have just spent several hours arguing with an economist - who receive positive
utility, at least for
a while, by acting 'irrationally'. What makes the assumption useful is that it describes fairly accurately the predictable element of human behavior.
People do, to a considerable extent, act rationally for reasonably simple goals; to the extent that they do so an economist
can predict their behavior.
This point is made very clearly by Alfred Marshall in
Chapter 2 of his Principles of Economics. Where, as in much of economic reasoning, all that matters is what most people do, or what people do on average, or what the predictable element
in people's action
is, the rationality axiom may lead to conclusions in which we have a good deal of confidence; even where it is important to know what a single person will do it may give us at least
a best guess. But the idea that economic
theory requires everyone
to act in a rational, predictable, calculable way all of the time is not economics but a parody of it, and one that has
often been used to ridicule economics
by those who neither understand nor believe in it.
Marshall Jevons has apparently not read Alfred Marshall. Professor Spearman's detective deductions depend
on the suspects behaving with perfect
rationality and having no innocent motives for their actions
save those immediately apparent. To pick an example almost
at random, Pro fessor Spearman
temporarily identifies a Harvard colleague
as the murderer on the grounds
that, on the night of the murder, he
drank less than usual - even though
the drinks, which he normally
had to pay for, were on that occasion free. No connection
is made between the murder (which occurred earlier in the day) and the suspect's sober violation of the law of demand.
A little while later an innocent explanation for the behavior
is discovered and Professor Spearman promptly concludes that the colleague (who is known to have disapproved of the victim and approved of the murder)
must be innocent.
Similarly, he concludes
that the victim's
widow must be innocent on the grounds that she could get more money by divorcing him and collecting alimony than by killing
him and collecting social security
survivor's benefits. It apparently does not
occur to him that the woman, who
dislikes her husband and is independently wealthy,
might have relevant arguments in her utility
function other than income.
Having said so much about what is wrong with Murder at the Margin, it may seem paradoxical to express my hope
that the author will try again.
The book is entertaining, and it succeeds
in teaching some bits and pieces
of elementary economics along the way; its faults stem from the difficulty of thinking up economic
explanations which are both
ingenious and correct, with the result that those which the author
does come up with are mostly either trivial or wrong. This is the same difficulty that confronts
the economist in his ordinary
work. The advantage Marshall Jevons has over
the rest of us is that he can invent his own facts and situations so as to make
them amenable to analysis.
If he does publish
a second book (and rumor has it that he intends to) there are two important changes I hope he will
make. The first is to recognize that economic arguments
rarely yield more than probabilities, and accordingly to make the solution less dependent on the idea that a single
'irrational' act is little short of proof positive of guilt. The second
is to draw his collection of 'economic observations of a great economist' from life
instead of from the opening
pages of an elementary text. There are, after all,
a number of great or at least near-great economists available to be studied, and those who are no longer living
have mostly written books.
It should be possible from those sources to compile some really ingenious applications of economics to the real world for Professor Spearman's use.
David Friedman
Center
for Study of Public Choice
Virginia
Polytechnic Institute and State University