Order Without the State: Theory, Evidence, and the Possible Future Of
This essay
consists of four
parts. Part I is an attempt to define government. Part II is a
brief sketch of
the evidence on whether and under what circumstances an anarchy,
a society without
a government, is workable. Part III provides a theoretical
discussion intended
to help make sense of the evidence, including a discussion of
possible reasons
for the nonexistence of an anarchy. Finally, part IV discusses
under what
circumstances and in what form stateless societies might come to
exist over the
next century or so.
I:
What is
Government, What is Anarchy?
An anarchy is a
society without a
government, so a discussion of anarchy requires a definition of
government.
Government cannot be defined by what it does, because all
functions of
government, including making and enforcing laws, have been, and
most are,
performed at some times and places by organizations that almost
nobody would
call governments.[1]
This is a
point I will discuss in more detail in parts II and III of this
essay. So it
makes sense to define government not by what functions it
provides but by how
it provides them.
Weber famously
described the
state as Òa human community that (successfully) claims the
monopoly of the
legitimate use of physical force within a given territory.Ó If
we omit the word
Òlegitimate,Ó no states exist, since no state succeeds in
eliminating all use
of physical force by others, whether muggers in Chicago or the
Mafia in Sicily.
But including ÒlegitimateÓ raises difficult problems. If we
interpret ÒlegitimateÓ as
ÒlegalÓ the definition is circular, since until we know what
organization
counts as the state we do not know what rules count as laws.
Further, there are
societies in which law is not viewed as the creation of the
state at
allÐincluding all traditional Islamic societiesÐhence where some
use of physical force by the state is seen as illegal and some
use by non-state
actors as legal. Defining ÒlegitimateÓ in normative terms raises
another set of
problems.
My preferred
solution is to
define rights in terms of the set of mutually recognized
commitment strategies
by which individuals constrain how other individuals act towards
them, and to
then define a government as an institution with regard to which
those strategies
do not apply, an institution which can violate what individuals
view as their
rights with regard to other individuals without setting off the
responses by
which such rights are normally defended. For a detailed
explanation of this
view of rights, readers may wish to look at my ÒA Positive
Account of Property
Rights.Ó[2]
What I offer here is only a sketch.
I start by
considering the way in
which property rights are enforced in (some) animal species,
especially many
birds and fishesÐterritorial
behavior. An individual in some way claims and marks a
territory. If another
individual of the same species and gender trespasses on the
territory he is
attacked by the owner, who will fight more and more desperately
the further
into the territory the trespasser comes. A fight to the death is
usually a loss
for both winner and loser, which gives a potential trespasser a
good reason to
retreat. Thus ownership is enforced by a mutually recognized
commitment
strategy.
Corresponding
behavior by humans,
generalized to apply to much more than territory, is observed in
many different
contexts. A famous experiment in behavioral economics
demonstrated that
individuals value items they possess much more than items they
do not possess,
even when the initial allocation of items was random.[3]
In international relations, we routinely observe states willing
to bear costs
in defending their territory out of proportion to the value of
the territory
defendedÐthe British war with Argentina over the Falklands being
a
striking modern example. And both casual observation and
introspection tell us
that while individuals defending what they see as their rights
against other
individuals are not willing to bear unlimited costsÐnot many of
us are
willing to fight to the death against an armed muggerÐthey are
willing to
bear costs out of proportion to the value directly threatened.
Such behavior
makes sense as a commitment strategy, since the knowledge that
an individual
will bear large costs in defending even small rights provides
other individuals
with a reasonÐoften although not always an adequate reasonÐnot
to
violate those rights, and as long as the right is not violated
it is not
necessary to bear large costs to defend it.
Starting with this
definition of
rights as based on mutually recognized commitment strategies, we
may define a
state or governmentÐI will use the terms interchangeablyÐas an
organization against which those commitment strategies do not
hold. Most of us
are willing to bear substantial costs defending ourselves from a
private robber
or an attempt by another individual to enslave us, even briefly.
Few of us are
willing to bear similar costs to defend ourselves from a tax
collector or
mandatory jury service. Even those who consider taxation morally
illegitimate
and so have no reservations about concealing taxable income when
they believe
that doing so is in their interest feel no commitment to do so
when it is not.
An anarchy, then,
is a society in
which there is no such organization, in which the commitment
strategies by which
we defend our rights, whatever we and other members of that
society consider
those rights to be, apply to all other individuals.
II.
The Evidence
Anarchies,
stateless societies,
exist in the historical record in two forms. The best known are
primitive
societies, of which the Comanche indians provide a good example.[4]
They functioned for well over a century, they succeeded
surprisingly well in
defending themselves (and attacking others) despite their
eventual defeat by a
vastly superior enemy, they had reasonably well defined rules of
behavior
enforced by private action, a system of private norms entirely
substituting for
a legal system.
The other sort of
stateless
societies are embedded societiesÐsubcultures that succeed in
enforcing
their own rules on their own members while to varying degrees
obeying or
evading the rules of the state within which they are located.
Modern examples
include the Rominchal gypsies in England[5]
and the inhabitants of modern-day Shasta County California.[6]
In these cases again, the equivalent of legal rules are enforced
by
decentralized private action, with no specially privileged
enforcer.
In addition to
stateless
societies, primitive or embedded, we also observe many examples,
ancient and
modern, of private arrangement substituting for what are usually
viewed as core
functions of the state. Both the making and the enforcement of
law, for
instance, exist in private as well as public forms. Commercial
arbitration has
been and is used to resolve a considerable proportion of legal
disputes, both
in contexts where it does and in others where it does not depend
on enforcement
by the state.[7]
Contracts
create legal rules between the contracting parties. Protection
against crime is
provided legally by Brinks guards and the manufacturers of
burglar alarms,
illegallyÐbut in a form much closer to the form provided by the
stateÐby the Sicilian Mafia.[8]
As recently as the 19th century, much of the circulating money
of both Scotland
and the U.S. consisted of privately issued banknotes.
What we do not
observe are modern
anarchies in the sense of modern, developed, fully independent
stateless
societies. That fact is, in my view, the strongest argument
against the
practicality of a stateless society replacing a modern state. To
see why the argument,
while strong, does not entirely rule out the possibility of
future
non-primitive anarchies, it is worth considering a somewhat
different set of
hypothetical institutions from a perspective two centuries in
our past
Suppose that in
1800 some political
theorist, inspired perhaps by the French and American
revolutions, proposes a
new and different form of political and social organization. Its
features
include not merely a democratic government with all adult male
citizens having
the right to vote, already an unusual arrangement, but voting
rights for women
as well, along with complete legal equality between men and
women. Its
government taxes and spends between a third and a half of all
income. The
polity has no state supported religion, considerable diversity
of religious
beliefs, and a sizable part of the population believing in no
religion at all.
To add additional, if implausible, interest to this imaginary
creation, it has
no serious restrictions on the sexual behavior of adult
citizens, no legal and
few social penalties for bastardy, and little more than token
enforcement of
either the stability or fidelity of marriage.
A well informed
18th century
scholar might be able to find precedents for one or another of
the features of
this bizarre hypotheticalÐwhether utopia or distopia could be a
matter of
dispute. He would, I think, have difficulty citing any past
society that
combined very many of them.[9]
He would thus have about as good reason to reject as impossible
what is now the
dominant social and political system of the developed world as a
modern scholar
would have to reject the possibility of a future stateless
society.
III:
Theory
In constructing a
theoretical
picture of a modern stateless society and using that theory to
explore the
possibility of future stateless societies, one faces two sets of
problems that
such a society must deal with. The first is how a legal
framework for trade,
contracts, human interaction could exist without a state to
maintain it, and
the associated stability problemÐhow such a framework could be
prevented
from collapsing into either chaos in one direction or a state in
the other. The
second is how, without a state, various useful functions of
current states
could be providedÐa monetary system, protection of rights, the
production
of public goods, including defense against foreign states.
Framework
and
Stability
A legal framework
has to solve
the problem of creating and enforcing legal rules that will bind
both parties
to a dispute. I sketched one possible solution over thirty years
ago.[10]
In the system I then described, each individual is the customer
of a private
rights enforcement agency which, in exchange for an annual fee,
agrees to
arrange for his disputes with other individuals to be settled
and the verdicts enforced.
It does so by contracting with every other such agency whose
customers have any
significant chance of interacting with its customers to specify,
for each pair
of agencies, a private court whose verdicts both agencies agree
to accept and
enforce.
In the absence of
a sovereign,
what enforces the contracts between the agencies? The answer is
that they are
enforced by reputation and the discipline of repeat dealings. An
agency that
adopts a policy of only abiding by court verdicts when they
favor its customers
will soon find no other agency willing to go to court with it.
Since violence
is both more expensive and less predictable in its outcome than
litigation,
such an agency finds itself at a serious competitive
disadvantage.[11]
In such a system,
law is produced
on the market by private courts, each of which seeks to create
legal rules that
the customers of the enforcement agencies will wish to live
under.[12]
I have argued elsewhere[13]
that the incentives created by that system would lead to a more
attractive
legal system than what is or can be expected to be created by
the incentives of
thoseÐjudges and legislatorsÐwho create current law. My purpose
here is more modestÐmerely to establish the possibility of an
enforced
legal framework without a state.
Would such a
framework be stable?
That depends in large part on whether the equilibrium of the
market I have
described contains few or many agencies. That, in turn, depends
on the size of
the market and the extent of economies of scale in the business
of settling
disputes and enforcing rights. If, in equilibrium, there are
only two or three
rights enforcement agencies, there is an obvious temptation
either for them to
merge into a government in order to improve their ability to
exploit their
customers or for the situation to devolve into civil war as one
or more
concludes that it can establish a monopoly by force.[14]
If, in equilibrium, there are hundred such agencies in a
territory similar to
that of a modern state, with several sufficiently local to be
available to the
typical customer, then neither approach is likely to be
workable.
What determines
economies of
scale in rights enforcement? The obvious answer is that, as in
other
industries, larger firms have both advantages, such as greater
internal
division of labor, and disadvantages, such as the increased
difficulty of
knowing and controlling what oneÕs subordinates are doing as the
number of
layers between the corporate president and the individual worker
increases.
Casual observation suggests that large police forces have no
obvious advantage
in cost of operation or quality of service than small ones.
Perhaps more
relevantly, the Sicilian Mafia, whose chief line of business is
private rights
enforcement, is made up of many small firms, not a few large
ones.[15]
There is one
special factor in
the rights enforcement industry, however. Consider two firms
with somewhat
different customer bases, bargaining over what courtÕs legal
system to agree
on. Firm A prefers one legal system, say one that permits
capital punishment
for murder. Firm B prefers a different system, one that does not
permit it.
Each firm
estimates the value to
its customers, and from that the increase it can expect in its
revenues, if it
can provide them with its preferred legal system. We expect,
along conventional
Coaseian lines, that they will agree on the system that
maximizes their
combined benefit. But while this provides a solution to the
allocational
problemÐwhat legal rule will existÐit leaves open the
distributional problem. If it turns out that a system with
capital punishment
is optimal for the pair of firms, is it achieved by firm A
paying firm B to
agree to it or by firm A rejecting firm BÕs offer to pay it to
accept the
alternative? Put differently, what is the starting point from
which the two
firms bargain?[16]
The theoretical
answer, I think,
is that while allocation comes out of a bargaining game leading
to an efficient
legal system, distribution comes out of a prior mutual threat
game among the
rights enforcement agencies. In such a game, one relevant factor
is an agencyÕs
ability, if bargaining fails, to employ force. Under many,
although not all,
military technologies, there are considerable economies of scale
in
warfareÐlarge armies can not only defeat small armies, they can
do so
while inflicting larger costs than they receive. Hence if the
ability to bully
other agencies, or resist bullying by other agencies, is a major
part of what
determines how well a rights enforcement agency functions, that
might lead to
substantial economies of scale which might make the system
unstable.
My guess is that
the ability to
use force against other agencies will not be an important
element of what
rights enforcement agencies produce in a funcitoning society of
this sort,
mostly because observation suggests a great deal of inertia in
such mutual
threat games. Consider the obvious example of international
relations, which
one could argue have very much the structure I have described.
We do not
observe that national boundaries shift a mile or two in one
direction or the
other every time one country launches a new battleship or raises
or lowers its
military budget. Nor do we observe that smaller nations
routinely pay tribute
to larger nations.
If I am correct
then, once the
sort of system I have described is well established, the
distributional outcome
will be determined not by a current mutual threat game based on
current
abilities to employ force but by the result of such a game
played out in the
distant past. Given a starting point, the obvious equilibrium is
one in which
any bargaining among agencies takes the continuance of the
existing terms as
the default. An agency that tries to use the threat of military
force to
unilaterally modify the rules in its favor is then seen as a
threat to the other
agencies which, in total, greatly outnumber it.[17]
The system should be stable, provided that the economies of
scale in the
business of rights enforcement itself do not go far enough to
produce a market
equilibrium with only a few firms.
Even if economies
of scale in the
application of force are not an important issue in an existing
anarchy,
however, they may provide a barrier preventing such an anarchy
from coming into
existence, since at that point threats of force are likely to
play a much
larger role.
Private
Substitutes
for Public Production
At a theoretical
level, the
problem of replacing useful government services with privately
produced
services comes down to the problem of market failureÐof
situations where
individual rationality fails to lead to group rationality.[18]
Familiar examples are the problem of producing a public good,
such as national
defense, basic scientific research or a radio broadcast, and the
problem of
dealing with externalities. It is often argued that since market
failure means that
some desirable goods and services will not be produced on the
private market,
they must be produced instead by the state. This argument
purports to both
explain the existence of the state and justify it.
There are two
responses. The
first is that, in many cases, an ingenious entrepreneur can find
a profitable
partial solution to the problem of market failure. A radio or
television
broadcast, for example, is a pure public good in the
conventional
senseÐthe producer cannot control who gets it and consumption by
one
individual does not interfere with consumption by another.
Nonetheless such
broadcasts are routinely produced privately, paid for by the
ingenious trick of
combining a public good with positive cost of production and
positive value to
the consumer with a public good with negative cost of production
and negative
value and giving away the package: program plus advertising.
Basic research may
be produced either as a source of valuable reputation for
scientists,
universities and firms or because those producing it will be
able to
appropriate some of the benefits through first mover
advantagesÐthe
scientists who develop a new idea will understand it better and
be better able
to exploit it than others. This is a point that has been
explored at greater
lengthy by Terence Kealey.[19]
It follows that while market failure on private markets will
lead to suboptimal
production, it may not, and frequently does not, lead to the
complete failure
to produce. There is some inefficiency but usually less than one
would at first
expect, since oneÕs first thoughts are unlikely to generate all
of the possible
ways of overcoming market failure. The classic example is
provided by CheungÕs
ÒThe Fable of the Bees,Ó[20]
which demonstrated that a particular problem of market failure
which J. E.
Meade, a prominent economist who later won a Nobel prize, had
offered as an
example of the sort that could not be privately dealt with, had
been being
privately dealt with on a routine basis for many decades before
Meade
discovered that doing so was impossible.
Other private
solutions occur
through voluntary non-commercial arrangements. One example would
be systems of
private norms.[21]
Another
would be open source software such as the Linux operating
system. In each case,
even though individuals are not in a position to appropriate the
full value of
what they do, they are in a position to get sufficient benefit
from doing
things to make it in their interest to do them.
The first response
to the problem
of market failure is that although it is a problem on private
markets, it need
not be a catastrophic problem. The second response is that
although market
failure is indeed a problem, government is not a solutionÐbecause market failure is not
limited to
private markets. Market failure arises in situations where one
individualÕs
acts produce costs for others that they need not assent to or
benefits for
which they cannot be charged. Such situations exist in private
markets but are
endemic in political markets. A voter who spends time and effort
figuring out
what candidate will best serve the public interest is producing
a public good
for a very large publicÐand because such goods are
underproduced,
rational voters are rationally ignorant. Similarly for
legislator, lobbyist,
and judge. Each is making decisions most of whose costs and
benefits go to
others, hence most have little incentive to make the optimal
decision. So
shifting production from political to private markets is likely
to reduce, not
increase, problems due to with market failure.[22]
While this
provides an argument
against the general superiority of states to anarchies, there
remains the
possibility of narrower arguments on the other side. The obvious
one is the
problem of national defense. Defense against nations is a public
good, it is successfullyÐalthough
perhaps inefficiently and/or suboptimallyÐproduced by many
existing
states, and it is a public good whose inadequate provision may
be catastrophic,
since it can lead to the disappearance of the inadequately
protected society.
Like other public
goods, national
defense may be privately provided. Under current institutions,
it is common for
supporters of a threatened state to volunteer for military
service on
unattractive terms, buy war bonds for patriotic rather than
financial reasons,
contribute privately owned weapons if there is an inadequate
supply of publicly
owned ones. In a stateless society, one can imagine a variety of
other
mechanisms by which some level of defense might be privately
produced.[23]
How successful such mechanisms would be depends in part on the
society, in
particular its level of patriotismÐif the term can be applied to
a patria without a
stateÐand on the size of the
external threat it must defend against relative to its own
resources. It is
easier to imagine a stateless U.S. defending itself against
Mexico today than a
stateless France defending itself against Germany in 1914.
Before leaving the
subject of
replacing services provided by government, it is worth noting
that not all of
the things governments do, not even all of the things that
practically everyone
expects governments to do, can be plausibly represented as the
production of
pubic goods or solutions to other forms of market failure. The
protection of an
individual against criminals, for instance, is not a public
good; a police
force can decide who is or is not to be protected, and in
practice police
forces often do. Similarly a private agency can, and private
agencies do,
protect those who pay them and not those who do not. Like many
private
activities, private protection against crime may produce
externalities,
positive or negativeÐmy protection agency may incapacitate the
criminal
whose next offense would have been against you or it may deter
him into
attacking you instead of me. But as long as the external costs
and benefits are
not too large compared to the internal ones, we can expect
private arrangements
to produce something close to the optimal resultÐcloser than we
have any
good reason to expect from political production.
A monetary system
is not a public
good either; currency, like other useful commodities, can be
privately produced
and exchanged. For a hundred and fifty years in the 18th and
19th centuries
Scotland maintained a private monetary system using banknotes
issued by
competing private banks. Insofar as circumstances have changed
since then, the
changes probably make such a system more workable, not less,
since our
technologies for communicating the information needed to keep
track of the
reliability of money issuers are very much better than those
available to the
contemporaries of Adam Smith.[24]
This brief
discussion of the
possibilities for a stateless society suggests two possible
reasons why such
societies could not exist in the modern world:
1. Under current
circumstances,
economies of scale in the rights enforcement industry go to a
size sufficiently
large to make the system unstable.
2. Under current
circumstances, a
stateless society is unable to adequately produce the public
good of defense
against nations.
It also suggests
several possible
reasons why they do not exist but could.
3. Economies of
scale are large
when such a system is coming into existence, for reasons
discussed above, but
much smaller once such a system has been for some time
established.
4. A stateless
society in the
process of forming cannot defend itself, but an established one
can, at least
if it has the good fortune not to be threatened by powerful and
aggressive
neighbors.
5. More generally,
it might be
that the system is stable in the sense of Nash equilibrium, but
that it does
not come into existence for much the same reason that English
drivers do not
shift to driving on the right side of the road, despite the
obvious advantages
of doing so: the move to a new equilibrium requires coordinated
change, and so
is a mistake for anyone who does it if others do not.
In The Moral
Basis of a
Backward Society, Edward
Banfield compared
two towns, one in Italy and one in the U.S., and argued that
they differed in
the sets of mutually consistent strategies followed in each.
Each
setÐbetray and donÕt trust, trust and donÕt betrayÐwas self
reinforcing, making both alternatives stable. Similarly, given
the set of
existing commitment strategies followed by the inhabitants of
existing states,
there may be no simple way of shifting to the different set in
which prevention
against rights violation is produced by voluntary interaction
among peers
rather than by an involuntary relation between sovereign and
subjects.
6. Stateless
societies do not
come into existence for ideological reasonsÐbecause too many
people
believe in the necessity of the state.
If 1 or 2 is the
case, then we
will not get stateless societies unless and until social and/or
technological
change makes it no longer the case. If 3, 4, 5 or 6 is the case,
we might get
such societies if a pathway exists, or comes to exist, for
moving to them from
where we now are.
The
Future
In this section I
will explore
three different possibilities for achieving a future stateless
society. The
first assumes that the problem is not in maintaining such a
society but in
bringing it into existence, and considers how that problem might
be solved. The
second describes how an embedded anarchy within modern societies
might come
into existenceÐarguably is coming into existenceÐand might
eventually become the dominant form of organization. The third
considers
possible technological changes that might reduce or eliminate
factors that
currently prevent stateless orders.
Fabian
Anarchy
In The Wealth of Nations, published in 1776, Adam Smith wrote that ÒTo expect, indeed, that the freedom of trade should ever be entirely restored in Great Britain is as absurd as to expect that an Oceana or Utopia should ever be established in it.Ó Within less than seventy years, due in part to SmithÕs influence, England had moved to free trade.
Currently, the governments of developed countries are large, actively interventionist, and democratic. The degree of intervention has varied over the past fifty years in both directionsÐincreased intervention in land use due largely to environentalist concerns, reduced regulation of transport industries both in the U.S. and elsewhere. One factor causing such changes is the opinion of academics, through their influence on both public and expert opinion, another is the public view, based in part on experience, of the relative advantages of government and private production.
One can imagine a future in which the prevalent views of some such societies, like those in England between 1776 and 1840, shift steadily in a direction opposed to government involvement. Consider schooling, currently the largest activity of state and local governments in the U.S. A full blown voucher system in which schooling subsidized by the state could be provided privately is well within the bounds of political possibility, although it has not yet come into existence. If such a system were introduced in one state and its success lets to its introduction in others, it might, over a period of a few decades, virtually eliminate public schooling. Once most parents were sending their children to privately run schools, there would be a strong argument for restricting public subsidy to poor parents, thus eliminating most of the government role in schooling.
One can imagine similar developments in other areas, including the replacement of much of the existing system of police and courts by private arrangementsÐeither private arrangements sanctioned by the state, such as current arbitration and the private police forces maintained by many colleges, universities, and gated communities, or unsanctioned arrangements as in modern Sicily.
Following out this
line of
development, one gets a future, sometime in the next century, in
which
government still exists but controls relatively little, with the
de facto legal
rules coming out of agreements among a network of private
enforcers and
arbitrators as descriped in the previous section of this essay.
At some point
in that future, government, whether or not it still exists on
paper, no longer
exists in fact. For an entertaining, if not very serious,
picture of such a
future, see Neal StephensonÕs novel Snowcrash.
Crypto-Anarchy
Online
An increasing part
of human
interaction, social and commercial, has shifted over the past
few decades from
realspace to cyberspace. Travel agents have been virtually
eliminated by online
competitors such as Travelocity.com, bookstores faced with the
competition of
Amazon.com, movies, amusement parks, television and other forms
of
entertainment in part replaced by massively multiplayer online
role playing
games such as World of Warcraft,
currently played by something over ten million people.
One attractive
feature of the
online world is that, within it, physical coercion is
impossible. One can fool
people or their computers, but one cannot get a bullet through a
T-1 line. It
is in that sense a world of entirely voluntary interaction. In
order to use
force against an online competitor or opponent, it is necessary
to shift the
conflict to realspaceÐsue him, assassinate him, arrest him.
Current encryption
technology
provides the tools with which it is possible to almost entirely
eliminate that
option. As pointed out long ago by computer scientist and sf
author Verner
Vinge,[25]
anonymity is the ultimate defenseÐyou cannot arrest someone if
you do not
know who he is. Public key encryption makes possible what I have
described
elsewhere as a world of strong privacy, a world in which it is
possible to
communicate with strangers in a form that no third party
observer can read,
establish oneÕs online identity in a way that no imposter can
imitate, link or
separate oneÕs online persona from oneÕs realspace persona as
desired, make
online payments with untraceable anonymous digital cash.[26]
While the full infracture required for such a world does not yet
exist, there
is no obvious reason why it cannot come into existence over the
next few
decades.
Within such a
world, government
can use force only against those who, by revealing their
realspace identity,
choose to make themselves vulnerable to it. It does not follow
that there will
be no ways of enforcing rules. Within a proprietary community
such as World
of Warcraft or Second
Life, the proprietors can
make rules and enforce them
against those who choose to enter that world.[27]
Outside of that framework, the technologies that make possible
strong privacy
also make possible forms of reputational enforcement of
contract that can
substitute for existing state enforcement.[28]
It thus seems
possible, even
likely, that within a decade or two large parts of human life in
developed
societies will become stateless, a system of voluntary
transactions enforced
entirely by competing private entities using reputational rather
than coercive
means of enforcement. At that point, what we will have will be
an embedded
anarchy available to much, perhaps almost all, of the population
of existing
developed states. As interaction through virtual reality becomes
better, a
process already occurring, the amount of life that can be
effectively lived in
cyberspace expands.
The larger the
role of online
anarchy in individual life, the weaker the power of realspace
states. If most
of my social and professional life occurs online, I can move
from one state to
another at little cost. If I am a valuable citizenÐone whose
taxes more than
pay for the costs he imposesÐsome states will have an incentive
to make
an effort to attract me. Competition among states for citizens
drives down the
ability of states to exploit their citizens. At the same time, a
world of
strong privacy almost entirely eliminates the stateÕs ability to
control
information, since information can be produced, exchanged,
bought and sold
online where the state cannot observe transactions. And if a
large fraction of
commercial transactions shift to a world of online anonymity,
the result is to
substantially reduce the stateÕs ability to collect taxes.
This suggests a
second possible
scenario for a continual shift towards a stateless future,
driven not by
beliefs but by technology.
Other
Technological
Possibilities
There are other
technological
developments that might, or might not, make realspace anarchy
more likely.
Consider, for instance, the division in present society between
tort law and
criminal law. Both depend on state enforcement of verdicts, but
only in the
case of criminal law does the state control the process that
leads to the
verdict; tort cases are privately prosecuted and can be
privately settled. A
shift from criminal law to tort law, a reversal of the legal
trend of the past
thousand years or so, would sharply reduce the role of the state
in law
enforcement and so make easier a transition to a fully private
system.
The question of
why some offenses
are handled by criminal law and some by tort law is a difficult
one,[29]
but one factor may be the cost of catching and convicting
criminals. If it is
larger than the amount of damages the loser of a tort case will
pay, whether
because of limits to his legal liability or limits to his
resources, it may not
be in the interest of the victim to sue.[30]
If that is the problem, then improved surveillance technology, a
change
currently occurring,[31]
may solve it. In a transparent society where everything that
happens in public
places, perhaps in private places as well, is observed,
recorded, and
searchable, most legal disputes may be reduced to disputes over
the legal
implications of known facts, thus eliminating a large part of
the cost of
current enforcement of law.
For a different
sort of change,
consider changes in the technology of violence which might alter
the balance
between offense and defense or the pattern of economies and
diseconomies of
scale in the production of military force. Or consider the way
in which
improved communications and transport may make national
boundaries increasingly
irrelevant, forcing an increasing fraction of transactions,
including legal
disputes, into non-state mechanisms. Or consider the effects of
increasing
levels of wealth and education. It is at least arguable that
modern democracies
donÕt attack each other. If so, and if in the future most power
is held by
democracies, and if the reasons for their restraint apply to
attacks on
developed stateless societies as well, the problem of national
defense may
become less critical in the future.
Finally, consider
the possibility
of seasteading[32]Ðfloating
housing
competitive with conventional housing, located either on the
high seas
or in the territorial waters of some friendly state. Like a
shift of life to
cyberspace, it increases mobility and thus increases the degree
to which states
must compete for citizens, weakening the power of the state. And
it offers the
possibility of floating stateless societies, with secession the
ultimate, and
easy, sanction.
None of these
provide confident
grounds to predict stateless societies in the next
centuryÐcyber-anarchy
is probably the closestÐbut they suggest a variety of possible
ways in
which such societies might come into existence.
David Friedman
School of Law
Santa Clara
University
Santa Clara, CA
95117
[1] ÒSociologically the state cannot be defined in terms of its ends. There is scarcely any task that some political association has not taken in hand, and there is no task that one could say has always been exclusive and peculiar to those associations which are designated as political ones: today the state, or historically, those associations which have been the predecessors of the modern state.Ó Weber
[2]
ÒA Positive Account
of Property Rights,Ó Social Philosophy and Policy 11 No. 2 (Summer 1994)
pp. 1-16. Webbed at:
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/Property/Property.html.
[3]
Kahneman,
D., J. Knetsch and R. Thaler, 1991, ÒExperimental Tests of the
Endowment Effect
and the Coase Theorem,Ó Journal of Political Economy, 98,
1990, pp:1325-1348
[4] E. Adamson Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man, Chapter 7.
[5]
Walter O.
Weyrauch, Gypsy Law: Romani Legal Traditions and Culture, Chapter 3.
[6]
Described by
Robert Ellickson, Order Without Law.
[7]
Lisa
Bernstein, ÒOpting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal
Contractual Relations in
the Diamond Industry," 21 Journal of Legal Studies 115 (1992).
Benson, B.
L. 1998. ÒLaw Merchant,Ó In P. Newman, (ed.). The New
Palgrave Dictionary of
Economics and the Law,
London: Macmillan
Press.
[8] Diego Gambetta, The Sicilian Mafia: The Business of Private Protection.
[9] Readers are invited to offer counterexamples.
[10]
David
Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical
Capitalism, part III.
[11] As I have pointed out elsewhere, we can observe a strategically equivalent game being played out in the real world. Just as a rights enforcement agency may deal with a conflict between its customer and the customer of another agency by either inexpensive agreement or expensive violence, so an auto insurance company may deal with an accident between its customer and the customer of a competitor by either inexpensive agreement or expensive litigation. Almost all such cases are settled outside of the courts.
[12] I am describing a polylegal systemÐthe legal rules between A and B need not be the same as between A and C or B and D. The same is true, although less obviously, in our legal system, where the outcome of a legal dispute may depend in part on what stateÕs courts or what federal district it is settled in, which itself may depend on the state citizenship of the parties, the physical location of the events that led to the dispute, and similar factors. It was more obviously true in medieval legal systems such as those of the Islamic world, where the outcome of a case might depend on the religion or ethnicity of the parties or on which of the four mutually orthodox Sunni legal schools they adhered to.
[13]
Friedman,
David, The Machinery of Freedom Chapters
29, 31, 32; also Friedman, David, ÒAnarchy and Efficient
LawÓ in For
and Against the State,
edited by Jack
Sanders and Jan Narveson, 1996.
[14]
Arguably
this is what eventually happened to the semi-stateless society
of saga period
Iceland during the Sturlung period. Friedman, David, ÒPrivate
Creation and
Enforcement of Law Ñ A Historical Case,Ó Journal of Legal
Studies, (March 1979),
pp. 399-415.
[15] Gambetts, The Sicilian Mafia. Some of the rights enforced by the Mafia are ones many of us disapprove of, such as the right to be protected from competition. But that is true of many of the rights enforced by states as wellÐarguably of more of them. Both my pieces of evidence involve rights enforcement by organizations with some degree of territorial monopoly, so raise the possibility of natural monopoly within a territory even if optimal territorial size is small. How serious a problem that would be for the sort of system I describe largely depends on how easily individual customers can change their company by changing their residence.
[16]
This point
was initially raised by James Buchanan in his (1974) "Review
of The
Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical Capitalism', Journal
of Economic
Literature, 12: 914-15.
[17] All of this is presented in terms of plausiblity arguments, not proofs, since game theory, in its present state of development, is strikingly short of convincing ways of proving what the result of strategic interactions will be.
[18]
For
discussions of the general problem see D. Friedman, Hidden
Order: The
Economics of Everyday Life, Chapter 18, and
the corresponding chapter of D. Friedman, Price
Theory: An
Intermediate Text,
webbed at:
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/Price_Theory/PThy_Chapter_18/PThy_Chap_18.html
[19]
Terence
Kealey, The Scientific Laws of Scientific Research.
[20] Steven N. S. Cheung, ÒThe Fable of the Bees: An Economic Investigation,Ó Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 16, No. 1 (Apr., 1973), pp. 11-33.
[21]
Eric A.
Posner, Law
and Social Norms, Robert
Ellickson, Order Without Law.
[22]
For a more
extensive discussion of this issue, see Friedman, David, Hidden
Order, Chapter 19, or
the corresponding chapter of Price
Theory, webbed at
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/Price_Theory/PThy_Chapter_19/PThy_Chap_19.html.
[23]
David
Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom,
Chapter 34. See also the suggestions in the piece webbed at
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/mps_iceland_talk/Iceland%20MP%20talk.htm
[24] Readers interested in a historical discussion should look at Lawrence White, Free Banking in Britain. For theoretical discussions see Friedman, David, ÒGold, Paper, Or...Is There a Better Money?Ó Cato Policy Analysis No. 17 (1982), webbed at http://www.cato.org/pubs/pas/pa017.html, and Friedman, David and Macintosh, Kerry, ÒTechnology and the Case for Free BankingÓ in The Half-Life of Policy Rationales: How New Technology Affects Old Policy Issues, edited by Fred Foldvary and Daniel Klein, New York University Press, New York, 2003.
[25] In the short story ÒTrue Names,Ó in True Names É and Other Dangers. Riverdale: Baen.
[26]
For details
see Friedman, David, "A World of Strong Privacy: Perils and
Promises of
Encryption," in Scientific Innovation, Philosophy, and
Public Policy, edited by
Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr.,
and Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge University Press 1996 (webbed at
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/Strong_Privacy/Strong_Privacy.html).
Chapter
3 of my forthcoming Future Imperfect (a draft is webbed at
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Future_Imperfect.html),
my ÒPrivacy
and TechnologyÓ in The
Right to Privacy, edited
by Ellen Frankel
Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge
University Press, 2000
(http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/Privacy%20and%20Technology.html).
[27]
Thus a world
with many such online proprietory communities looks rather
like the Utopia
described by Robert Nozick in Anarchy, State, and UtopiaÐan environment with a wide variety of
different social
systems among which each individual is free to choose.
[28]
For details,
see my "Contracts in Cyberspace," Journal of Internet Law,
December
2002. Webbed at:
http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Academic/contracts_in_%20cyberspace/contracts_in_cyberspace.htm.
[29]
For an
extended discussion see my LawÕs Order,
Chapter 18, ÒThe Crime/Tort Puzzle.Ó
[30]
One
possible solution to this problem is to pre-commit as a way of
producing
private deterrence; see Friedman, David, ÒMaking Sense of
English Law
Enforcement in the Eighteenth Century,Ó The University of
Chicago Law School
Roundtable (Spring/Summer 1995): 475-505.
[31]
Brin,
David, The Transparent Society. See also
the discussion in Friedman, David, Future
Imperfect (forthcoming
from Cambridge University Press).
[32]
For more
information, see http://seastead.org/.
For a
discussion of the high seas as a presently existing stateless
order, see The
Outlaw Sea: A World of Freedom, Chaos and Crime by William
Langewiesche.