Why Burglary Should be a Tort and Collision a Crime

(unpublished article)


If someone breaks your arm you call a cop; if he breaks a contract with you you call a lawyer. More generally, our legal system provide two different sets of rules for dealing with acts by which one individual harms another--tort law and criminal law. Both are similar in general outlines: someone attempts to demonstrate that a wrong has been done, and if he succeeds bad things happen to the offender, a possibility which makes the commission of wrongs less attractive. But they differ very much in the details. A tort claim belongs to the victim--it is he who prosecutes it, collects the damage claim if he wins, and has the legal power to settle. A criminal case belongs to the state.

This dual system for prosecuting wrongs raises a number of interesting questions. The first is whether there is any good reason to have two separate systems of rules; whether, for example, a legal system in which burglars and murderers were sued instead of arrested would be workable.
[1] The second is why the particular sets of rules go together in the way they do--why, for example, a system in which offenses are privately prosecuted is also one in which the victim collects the fine and in which guilt is proved by a preponderance of the evidence.[2] The third, and the question which which this note is concerned, is how offenses ought to be sorted between the two systems: what should be a tort and what should be a crime.

All three questions are complicated by the fact that legal rules affect behavior on many margins. They affect the incentives to commit offenses, the incentives to prosecute offenses, and the incentives to prevent offenses. It is possible, even likely, that for some offenses tort law will provide better incentives than criminal law on one of those margins and worse incentives on another. If so, the question of what ought to be a tort and what ought to be a crime will be ambiguous, at least until we develop a theory good enough to predict not only the sign but also the size of such effects.

My purpose here is simple. I wish to take one of the margins and argue that, judged by the incentives provided by the alternative legal systems on that margin, our legal rules are backwards. Things we treat as crimes, such as burglary, ought to be torts; things we treat as torts, such as auto accidents, ought to be crimes.

The incentive I have chosen to examine is the incentive that potential victims have to prevent offenses. Seen from that perspective, there is a simple and striking difference between tort law and criminal law. The victim of a tort suffers an injury but he also obtains an asset--a claim for damages against the offender. The victim of a crime suffers an injury but obtains no corresponding asset since the fine for the offense, if any, will go to the state, not to him.
[3] It follows that one effect of treating an offense as a tort instead of a crime is to reduce the net damage suffered by the victim, and thus his incentive to prevent the offense.

Reducing the incentive to prevent the offense is not necessarily a bad thing; here as elsewhere, what we want is the right incentive, neither too much nor too little. The ideal legal system, seen from this standpoint, is one in which the potential victim receives the net social benefit produced by his defensive precautions. The question for any particular class of offense is whether the reduction in incentive provided by tort law moves the potential victim towards or away from the efficient level of precaution.

A World of Costless Enforcement


In trying to answer that question, it is useful to start with a model of law enforcement in which catching and punishing offenders is costless. All offenders are detected, and none of them are judgement proof. Within this simplified framework, what is the right incentive, and what system gives it?

Start with automobile accidents. For simplicity, consider accidents in which a car runs over a pedestrian and only the pedestrian is injured. We may attempt to deter such accidents either with a tort rule, in which the driver of the automobile is liable to the victim for the damage done, or with a criminal rule, in which the driver pays a fine but the victim does not receive it.

From the standpoint of the driver, the two rules (with the same penalty) generate the same incentive. Any reduction in the probability of an accident due to the driver’s production reduces his liability by an amount equal to the savings in net social cost. What about the pedestrian?

Under the tort rule, the pedestrian suffers no cost from being run over, since his damages are fully compensated by the driver.
[4] It follows that the pedestrian has no incentive to take precautions. Under the criminal rule, on the other hand, the pedestrian pays the full cost of the accident. It follows that he has the efficient incentive to take precautions to prevent it.[5] It follows that, from the standpoint of the incentive for victim precautions, such offenses should be crimes, not torts.

Generalizing beyond the simplified example in which only one party suffers a loss, the efficient rule is that each party bears his own loss and pays a fine equal to the loss that the accident imposes on the other party. Thus each bears the full cost of the accident and has an incentive to take any cost justified precautions to reduce its probability.

Consider next the offense of burglary--again in a world of costless enforcement. The legal system sets the penalty for burglary equal to the damage done--the value of what is stolen. Any burglar willing to pay that price commits an offense--and should. The system generates only efficient burglaries--those where the gain to the offender is greater than the loss to the victim. The textbook example, due to Judge Posner, is the hunter, lost and starving, who comes across a locked cabin in the woods, breaks in, feeds himself, and telephones for help.

In this world, a homeowner who puts a lock on his door is wasting his own money and the burglar’s time. He is better off leaving the door open and (costlessly) collecting the value of whatever goes out. The optimal level of precaution to prevent burglary is the same as the optimal level of precaution for a supermarket to take in preventing its customers from buying its vegetables--zero.

Under a tort rule, that is the level of precaution that the victim will take. He knows he will be fully reimbursed for whatever he loses, so has no incentive to spend resources preventing burglary. Under a criminal rule, on the other hand, the criminal takes from the victim but repays the state, so the victim has an incentive to prevent the burglary. Hence, at least in the simplified world of costless enforcement, and considering only the incentive of the victim to defend himself, burglary ought to be a tort.

A Formal Treatment


To see the underlying difference between an auto accident and a burglary, it is useful to express both in the same form. We have two parties, each of whom can spend resources affecting the probability that an event--an auto accident or a successful burglary--will occur. If we define E1 as expenditure by party 1 and E2 by party 2, and C1,2 similarly as the cost to each party of the event occuring, p (E1,E2) as the probability of the event, we have, absent any legal rules:

Net Cost to party 1 absent legal rule =E1+C1p(E1,E2)

Net Cost to party 2 absent legal rule =E2+C2p(E1,E2)

We wish the efficient level of precautions, the level that minimizes the summed cost:

Net cost to both parties = E1+ E2+ [C1+C2]p(E1,E2)

Giving us the first order marginal conditions:

1+ [C1+C2]p1(E1,E2)=0 (Equation 1a)

1+ [C1+C2]p2(E1,E2) (Equation 1b)

Party 1 controls E1, party 2 controls E2, and each wishes to minimize his net cost. We generate the efficient marginal conditions 1a,b by a legal rule which, if the event occurs imposes a fine of C2 on party 1 and a fine of C1 on party 2, generating new net costs:

Net Cost to party 1 absent legal rule =E1+C1p(E1,E2)
Net Cost to party 1 with optimal rule =E1+ [C1+C2] p(E1,E2)

Net Cost to party 2 with optimal rule =E2+ [C1+C2] p(E1,E2)

The levels of E1,2 that minimize the new net costs also satisfy Eqns 1a,b.

Seen from this perspective, all three of our cases are the same. In the auto/pedestrian case, C1=0, C2>0, so we get the efficient outcome by fining the driver for the damage done to the pedestrian. In the more general case of mutual damage, for instance an auto/auto collision, C1,2>0 and we fine both drivers when an accident occurs. In the burglary case, with party 1 the victim and party 2 the burglar, C1>0, C2<0, since the burglar receives a benefit from a successful burglary. So the efficient rule punishes the burglar with a fine equal to the value of the amount stolen and rewards the victim with a subsidy also equal to the amount stolen. In other words, the efficient rule is a damage payment rather than a fine.

The attentive reader may wonder why I assume that the benefit to the burglar is equal to the loss to the victim--after all, one of the reasons we ban theft is that goods are usually worth more to their present owner than to the thief. But I am considering an efficient system with costless punishment. Since the burglar is paying a fine equal to the victim’s cost, he will not steal unless the good is worth at least that much to him.

There remains the possibility that, as in the starving hunter example, the gain to the burglar may be larger than the loss to the victim. To adequately take account of this possibility, one requires tort law plus a subsidy to the victim representing the average gain to the burglar from stealing, net of the fine he pays. The simple tort rule gives the correct answer only for the marginal burglar, and is thus correct at most for precautions that, like a small increase in punishment, deter only marginal burglars. Even in that case, the analysis is complicated by the possibility that a precaution that deters marginal burglars raises the cost to all burglars, and thus imposes an external cost on the undeterred burglaries.

A World With Enforcement Costs


The analysis becomes more complicated in a world with enforcement costs--costs of catching and punishing
[6] an offender. In such a world, precautions by the victim of burglary produce benefits as well as costs. If the optimal effective punishment is less than damage done--if, in other words, we are permitting some inefficient offenses because deterring them costs more than it is worth[7]--then precautions prevent some inefficient offenses. In addition, precautions reduce the number of offenses and thus the cost of apprehending and punishing offenders.

It remains true that preventing burglaries imposes a cost on burglars which an efficient system of incentives ought to take into account. It could do so by awarding victims damages representing the value to the offender of his offense net of the cost of apprehending and punishing him. That, roughly speaking, is what a tort system does, since the victim must pay his own litigation fees and bears the risk that the defendant may be judgement proof.

Readers interested in a more complete analysis of this problem may either await a later revision of this essay or look at an earlier article
[8] in which I proposed and analyzed a system of legal rules designed to provide private enforcement of what is currently criminal law--a sort of expanded tort system. In that system, victims of crimes were able to sell their claim against the offender for a price representing the amount of his punishment net of the cost of catching and punishing him. I argued there that, if one assumed away a variety of potential sources of market failure affecting the level of precaution taken by potential victims,[9] that set of institutions leads to an optimal level of precaution.


[1]I discuss a real world system of this sort in some detail in "Private Creation and Enforcement of Law : A Historical Case." Journal of Legal Studies, (March 1979), pp. 399-415.
[2]For an example of a real world system which in most ways resembled our criminal system but in which offenses were privately prosecuted, see D. Friedman, "
Making Sense of English Law Enforcement in the Eighteenth Century," The University of Chicago Law School Roundtable (Spring/Summer 1995).
[3]This is a slight oversimplification. In many cases, the victim of a crime is also the chief witness. In such cases, a de facto out of court settlement becomes possible; the defendant compensates the victim and the victim stops cooperating with the police. One plausible explanation of why the tort system gives the claim to the victim instead of, say, auctioning it off to the highest bidder is that the victim, because he is already the chief witness, is also the person with the highest value for the claim. A second reason why he might be expected to have the highest value is because his incentives include both collecting a damage payment and establishing a reputation to deter future offenders.
[4]One of the odd features of a system of costless enforcement is that all injuries can be compensated. For a more realistic analysis of the problem of how to treat death and bodily injury in a system of tort law, see D. Friedman, "
What is Fair Compensation for Death or Injury?" International Review of Law and Economics, 2, (1982), pp. 81-93.
[5]I believe that this point was first noted in an old article by Earl Thompson, but I do not yet have the cite.
[6]Note that punishment costs include costs to the offender. A costlessly collected fine has punishment cost of zero, a costlessly imposed execution has punishment cost equal to amount of punishment equal to one life, and imprisonment has punishment cost greater than amount of punishment--the cost of imprisonment to the offender plus the cost to others of maintaining the prison.
[7]For the formal analysis of the problem of optimal enforcement, see Friedman, D. "
Should the Characteristics of Victims and Criminals Count? Payne v Tennessee and Two Views of Efficient Punishment," Boston College Law Review XXXIV No.4, pp.731-769 (July 1993), "An Economic Explanation of Punitive Damages," Alabama Law Review, Volume 40 Number 3, Spring 1989, pp. 1125-1142, "Reflections on Optimal Punishment or Should the Rich Pay Higher Fines?," Research in Law and Economics, (1981). All three articles contain explanations of essentially the same analysis. The conclusion is that the optimal effective punishment (the certainty equivalent of the punishment lottery imposed on the offender) is equal to the damage done by the offence minus the marginal cost of deterrence--the increase in apprehension, litigation, and punishment cost required to deter one more offense.
[8]D. Friedman, "
Efficient Institutions for the Private Enforcement of Law." Journal of Legal Studies, June (1984).
[9]For instance, the possibility that precautions taken by one potential victim may impose net costs on another, by deterring the criminal into altering his target, or net benefits, if the criminal knows the average level of precaution but not which targers are protected.