Lecture Notes
Economic Analysis of Law
Spring 1997
Santa Clara University
Department of Economics
Professor D. Friedman
[These notes will be updated about every week]
- 0. Course
structure
- A. One midterm, one final, no papers, no
homework.
- B. Three sources of written
information.
- 1. Posner text.
- a. Nearest thing available to a survey of law and
economics
- b. Much too much stuff for a one quarter text.
- c. But useful both as a supplement to the lectures
and a source of additional material for those who are
interested.
- 2. Lecture notes: Will be distributed weekly in hardcopy
and put on the web page (with links to other relevant
material on my web site).
- 3. Articles: Copycraft.
Some are also on
my web page, linked to the class page.
- I. What does economics have to do with law?
- A. Two views of a traffic ticket:
- 1. A way of transferring money from drivers to
governments--a rather peculiar tax.
- 2. A way of giving people an incentive not to drive too
fast.
- B. More generally, think of law as a system
of incentives.
- C. Economics is about the
implications of individual rationality
- 1. Do we believe that
criminals
are rational?
- a. Muggers pick on little old ladies, not football
players, which suggests they are trying to get money at
the lowest cost practical.
- b. Burglars tend to avoid burgling houses with people
in them in areas where people frequently own guns.
- c. Statistical evidence suggests that raising the
expected punishment for an offense tends to reduce the
number of offenses.
- 2. How about the rest of us--drivers, potential victims,
litigators, ... . Econ analysis of law is about us too.
- D. Hence about how rational individuals
will respond to the incentives created by legal rules.
- II. What is the
economic analysis of law?[See
article]
- A. Using economics to deduce the
consequences of legal rules.
- 1. Marginal deterrence example:
- a. Suppose we raise the penalty for armed robbery to
the highest level our legal system permits.
- b. A legal philosopher would ask "is this just?"
- c. An economist would ask "do we want armed robbers
to routinely kill the witnesses?" since ...
- d. One result of the change is to eliminate the
penalty for murder--if you are already committing an
armed robbery.
- 2.
Plea
bargaining example:
- a. A criminal will only accept a plea bargain if he
prefers it to the punishment lottery (some probability of
some punishment) that he faces if he goes to trial, so
...
- b. It looks as though plea bargaining reduces average
punishment, but ...
- c. Not if you allow for the fact that a prosecutor
who settles many of his cases by plea bargaining has more
resources left to prosecute the cases that don't settle,
which raises the probability of conviction, which makes
people willing to accept harsher plea bargains, so ...
- d. Permitting plea bargaining might increase average
punishment.
- 3.
Freedom
of contract example:
- a. Fixing one term of a contract, for instance
requiring landlords to give tenants six months notice
before evicting them, looks as though it benefits one
party (tenants) at the cost of another (landlords), but
...
- b. If you allow for the effect that fixing that term
has on the other terms (market rents rise in the
example), the net effect may well be to make both sides
of the contract worse off,
- c. By forcing them to include inefficient terms in
their contract--which the "benefitted" party ends up
paying more for than they are worth.
- d. This suggests a general presumption in favor of
the principle of freedom of contract--let the courts
enforce contracts as written, rather than deciding what
terms the parties ought to have agreed to.
- B. Using economics to predict and
understand rules.
- 1. The Posner Thesis:
- a. Posner conjectures that common law (judge made)
legal rules tend to be economically efficient.
- b. Testing the conjecture has played a major role in
the development of economic analysis of law.
- 2. Special interest politics is an
alternative
theory for explaining what laws, especially laws made by
legislatures, are like.
- C. Using economics to choose legal
rules.
- 1. Designing efficient rules.
- 2. Is that worth doing?
- 3. Part of the attraction of the economic analysis of
law is that you get out more than you put in.
- a. We start by assuming that values to thieves and
murderers count just like values to anyone else.
- b. We conclude that theft and murder ought to be
illegal--because even if you count the benefit to the
criminal, permitting crimes still turns out to be
inefficient.
- D. Part of why it is exciting is that it
may provide a theoretical core for law.
- 1. Traditional legal theory isn't a theory--it is the
theory of property law, the theory of tort law, the ..., not
any unifying theory that makes sense of the whole thing.
- 2. Economic analysis of law shows that the same
analysis, concepts, problems, ... apply across all of law.
- [What we are doing for the first two
weeks: Sketching out the theoretical arguments that will underly
the analysis of lots of legal issues. ]
- III. What is economic
Efficiency[Longer explanation]
- A. The problem: We want a single criterion
to define "better" and "worse" for a whole society.
- 1. How do we judge better and worse for a single
individual?
- 2. How do we aggregate.
- 3. What is the upper bound--what defines "efficient" as
opposed to "more efficient."
- B. Marshall's solution:
- 1. Individual values are defined by revealed
preference--what you would pay for an outcome if you had to.
- 2. We aggregate values by summing individual values,
measured in dollars--how much I would pay plus how much you
would pay plus ... .
- 3. We use a Bureaucrat God as a definition of the upper
bound of efficiency
- a. An imaginary central planner
- b. Who knows everything anyone in the society knows
- c. And has unlimited ability to calculate what should
be done and make us do it.
- d. An efficient outcome is one that cannot be
improved (i.e. aggregate value cannot be increased) even
by a bureaucrat god.
- e. Note that the term "bureaucrat god" is my
invention--don't blame Marshall for it.
- C. Objections:
- 1. Insulin and heroin--are both of value, judged by
people's willingness to pay for them. In other words, we are
measuring what people do value, judged by their actions, not
what we think they should value.
- 2. Rich and poor: We are treating a dollar gain or loss
to a rich person as just as important as a dollar gain or
loss to a poor person, although most of us suspect that a
dollar usually represents more happiness for the poorer
person.
- 3. Our upper bound is unattainable, since we have no
bureaucrat gods, so why use it to define "efficient?" Isn't
the result that all possible institutions are inefficient?
- D. Can you do better?
- 1. Revealed preference is there to drive your
institutions--anything else requires someone else second
guessing individual preferences. I may not always know what
is in my interest--but I can be trusted to want what is in
my interest more than other people can be trusted to want
what is in my interest.
- 2. Ditto for rich and poor, also ...
- 3. It is hard to use legal institutions to redistribute,
and ...
- 4. Not clear that if you can, you will do it the right
way or at reasonable cost.
- 5. Upper bound is useful as a maximum--and an idealized
market achieves it!
- E. It is important to understand the idea
of economic efficiency, whether or not you agree with
it.
- 1. Because asking the question "what rules would be
efficient" turns out to be an interesting way of
understanding the law.
- 2. So take it as a working hypothesis, feel free to drop
it at the end of the quarter.
- IV. Why markets are
efficient:[Longer explanation from my book]
- A. The simple argument:
- 1. If the individual making a decision bears all of the
costs and receives all of the benefits, then he takes the
act which maximizes (private benefit-private cost) which
equals (total benefit-total cost), hence he takes the
efficient act.
- 2. This still works as long as net private benefit=net
total benefit.
- a. Suppose A's action harms B by $10 and benefits C
by $10--the two effects net out to zero, so he still
makes the right choice.
- b. Example: I become the 1001'st physician. The cost
of a medical visit falls by ten cents as a result. That
is a loss to the other 1000 physicians--exactly balanced
by a gain to their customers.
- B. Consider an ordinary market
transaction
- 1. Buying a good--you pay the price, receive the
benefit.
- 2. Producing a good--you pay the cost of the inputs,
receive the benefit in the price.
- C. For this argument to work, however, you
have to show that the price I pay really represents the human
cost of using the good, the price I receive represents the
benefit produced by the good, so that "cost" in the sense I see
it (dollars)= "cost" in the sense relevant for economic
efficiency (value forgone from other ways of using the input,
value of the output).
- D. Price theory does that. See my book,
on-line.
- E. But ...
- V. Individual
rationality vs group rationality:
- A. Armies
running away.
- 1. Each individual is behaving rationally
- 2. Yet all of them are worse off than if they behaved in
a different way.
- B. Rational pollution.
- 1. There are a hundred individuals, each of whom can
burn cheap coal or expensive gas to heat his house.
- 2. The coal pollutes, but ...
- 3. 99% of the pollution produced by my coal burning is a
cost for other people, so I only count 1% of it, so ...
- 4. I burn coal even if the total cost, including the
pollution, is substantially larger than for gas.
- 5. Note that, on net, we are all worse off. I am
externalizing 99% of the cost of my pollution, but paying 1%
of the cost of the pollution by each of the other 99 people.
- 6. But on the margin--the margin of how much I
pollute--the pollution cost is almost all external.
- C. More generally, externalities lead to
inefficient outcomes.
- VI. One approach to
dealing with such problems which we will mostly ignore until near
the end of the course is by systems of
private
norms: If you pollute, your
neighbors will think you are a bad neighbor and treat you
accordingly, or you will think you are a bad citizen of the earth
and feel guilty.
- A. This can work pretty well for norms such
as honesty and courtesy, which involve things that individuals
can directly observe and know about, but ...
- B. Not so well for big issues such as
global warming or recycling, since the individual who is
"enforcing" the norms has no direct information on what actions
actually do good or damage and how much:
- 1. CO2 emissions leading to a greenhouse effect may be a
bad thing if you live in (low-lying) Bangladesh, but they
make it easier to live in (cold) Canada, and they make
agriculture more productive, since CO2 is an input to
photosynthesis.
- 2. Recycling paper may reduce the amount of U.S. forest,
since reducing the demand for pulpwood makes it less
profitable to use land to grow trees on.
- 3. For similar reasons, the ivory ban might reduce the
number of elephants.
- VII. Externalities: The central planning solution:
- A. EPA calculates the cost imposed by a
factory polluting, the cost of preventing it, permits it if
banning it produces net cost. but ...
- B. How can they have the information
necessary to do that?
- 1. In particular, how can they know the cost to
polluters of controlling, by ...
- a. Pollution control
- b. Alternative production methods
- c. Not producing the good at all, or producing less.
- 2. When the person with the best information about cost
of controlling pollution is the producer, and it is in the
producer's interest to argue that there are no cost
justified ways of controlling the pollution, since then he
will be allowed to continue polluting.
- C. Even if they did the calculation
correctly for the firm itself, if it is allowed to pollute
(because doing so is efficient), the price of its output will
not include all of the cost imposed, so everyone else will be
using an inefficiently large quantity. So they really have to
do the calculation for the whole economy, not just a single
firm--and then tell the firms that are allowed to pollute how
much output (the efficient quantity) they are allowed to
produce.
- D. And what makes it in EPA's interest to
act that way, even if they can?
- 1. Economics is supposed to apply rationality to
everyone.
- 2. So we really need a theory of the political
marketplace; for some pieces of one, see my book.
- VII. Externalities, the Pigouvian solution:
- A. Impose an effluent fee equal to the
damage done by the pollution.
- B. The firm is thus forced to internalize
the externality--its costs, including the effluent fee, now
equal the total cost imposed by its action.
- 1. So it chooses the efficient alternative.
- 2. Controls pollution if doing so is worth the cost
- 3. Switches to alternative production methods if that is
cheaper
- 4. Closes down if cost is now greater than what the
customers will pay.
- 5. Note that the fine might go to the state, as in this
example, or to the victim, as in tort law. We will discuss
later why it matters which it is.
- C. Furthermore, the pollution cost is now
included in the price for the firm's output, so everyone
downstream has the right incentives.
- D. Problem solved--until 1960, when Coase
published "The Problem of Social Cost."
- VIII. The Coaseian
critique: Act I: Nothing Works
- A. There is a small private lake; half the
shore belongs to a chemical factory, half to a fishing resort,
nobody else uses it.The factory's pollution kills most of the
fish, reducing the resort's revenue from $50,000/year to
$10,000/year.
- 1. So we charge the factory $40,000/yr effluent fee.
- 2. Stopping the pollution only costs $30,000/yr, so the
factory stops polluting, but ...
- 3. The resort could switch to a riding resort, with no
fishermen, and make $40,000/year.
- 4. So "No pollution/fishing" solution costs $30,000/year
to factory
- 5. "pollution/riding" costs $10,000/yr lost revenue to
the resort
- 6. We have gotten the inefficient outcome.
- B. The general argument is that an
externality is not a cost A imposes on B, but a cost jointly
due to decisions by A and B.
- 1. Air pollution in Los Angeles wouldn't be a problem if
nobody lived there. If that seems unreasonable, consider ...
- 2. Dropping bombs next to people camping on bombing
ranges imposes externalities on the campers, but it seems
likely that moving the campers is the cheaper solution.
- 3. Simple case of two roommates: My playing loud music
imposes a cost on you when you want to sleep. But if the
rule is "I can't play when you want to sleep," then your
sleeping imposes a cost on me--I can't play loud music when
you're sleeping.
- a. If I can play the music even if you want to sleep,
I will sometimes due so inefficiently (when the cost
imposed on you is more than the benefit to me)
- b. If I can't play it when you are sleeping, you will
sometimes sleep inefficiently (when ... ).
- C. Coase offers some interesting real world
examples:
- 1. The physician and the candy factory.
- 2. Chimneys not drawing after the building next door was
rebuilt--higher.
- 3. Stopping up the vent by which brewery fumes escaped
--via an old mining tunnel--from a basement brewery.
- 4. A new building shading a hotel swimming pool.
- D. The implication of this argument is that
nothing works.
- 1. In setting general rules, such as "polluters must pay
a fine equal to damage done," the legal system does not know
which party can adjust at lower cost.
- 2. If it makes the wrong party liable, that party may
adjust, so the other party has no incentive to.
- 3. And the optimal solution might involve adjustments by
both parties.
- E. Think of the question as "how do we
bundle property rights."
- 1. Does my ownership of part of the lakeshore imply the
right to pollute, or the right not to have the lake
polluted?
- 2. Does my ownership of the hotel pool include ownership
of the sunlight falling on it?
- 3. Who owns the right to control the movement of
currents of air--the air carrying the smells from the
brewery into someone else's courtyard, or carrying (or not
carrying) the smoke from my chimney away?
- 4. Frat house and recording studio--does a landlowner
have a right to make noise or be free from noise?
- 5. How should we decide such questions? That is where
the Coaseian argument is leading.
- IX. Act II: Everything works.
- A. Back to the factory and the resort--plus
bargaining.
- B. The Coase Theorem: Any initial
assignment of rights will lead to an efficient outcome,
provided that transaction costs are zero.
- 1. Not always the same outcome--does the candy factory
or the physician have to pay the other to get his way?
- 2. Which matters for the distribution of income, if we
take nominal property holdings (who owns this piece of land)
as fixed, because we are changing actual property holdings
(who owns which rights with regard to the land).
- 3. It matters for the use of resources only if the
owners are also the consumers.
- a. A hermit who neither has nor wants much money
lives on the shore of the lake and loves having an
unpolluted lake to look at. If the factory has a right to
pollute, the hermit will not offer the factory enough to
make it in their interest to stop polluting. But if the
hermit has the right not to have the lake polluted, the
factory will not offer the hermit enough to get his
permission to let them pollute.
- b.In such a situation, we have different uses of
resources according to who starts with the rights--but
both outcomes are efficient!
- c. After all, how your desires get weighted in
determing the efficient outcome depends in part on how
much money you have, and different initial allocations
correspond to different distributions of wealth.
- d. If the hermit owns the right to decide that the
lake won't be polluted, he is richer than if he doesn't,
and the efficient outcome therefore gives more weight to
his preferences.
- e. Just as, in a world where I happen to own downtown
San Jose, somewhat more of goods I very much like will be
produced.
- X. It all depends--on transaction costs. Consider one factory and twenty resorts.
- A. Factory has a property right--it is free
to pollute and not liable for the results of its
pollution.
- 1. Without transactions, the factory pollutes whether or
not doing so is efficient.
- 2. With transactions,
- a. resorts face a public good problem in raising the
money to pay the factory not to pollute.
- b. Because if the factory stops polluting, all
resorts benefit, whether or not they helped pay.
- B. Factory pays a fine equal to the damage
done by its pollution.
- 1. No transactions are possible.
- a. If damage done by the pollution is <cost of
controlling it, factory continues to pollute, fishing
resorts switch to riding resorts, efficient outcome.
- b. If damage done>cost of controlling>cost of
switching to riding, the factory stops polluting, the
resorts don't switch, inefficient outcome--or ...
- c. The factory keeps polluting for a while, the
resorts switch, the fine falls, efficient outcome via
strategic behavior by factory.
- d. If damage done>cost of switching to riding
>cost of controlling>, the factory stops polluting,
the resorts don't switch, efficient outcome--or ...
- e. The factory keeps polluting for a while, the
resorts switch, the fine falls, inefficient outcome via
strategic behavior by factory.
- 2. Transactions are possible.
- a. If damage done by the pollution is <cost of
controlling it, factory continues to pollute, fishing
resorts can't make any offer to control pollution that
the factory would accept, efficient outcome.
- b. If damage done>cost of controlling>cost of
switching to riding, the factory pays the resorts to
switch to riding, efficient outcome--or ...
- c. The factory keeps polluting for a while, the
resorts switch, the fine falls, efficient outcome via
strategic behavior by factory.
- d. If damage done>cost of switching to riding
>cost of controlling, the factory stops polluting, the
resorts don't switch (there is no price the factory would
offer that they would accept), efficient outcome--or ...
- e. The factory keeps polluting for a while, the
resorts switch, the fine falls, inefficient outcome via
strategic behavior by factory. Or the resorts pay the
factory to stop polluting--but again face the public good
problem.
- C. Factory pays a damage payment to the
resorts for the damage done by its pollution.
- 1. This is like B above, except that
- 2. Strategic behavior by the factory doesn't work,
because the resorts are getting paid for the damage done,
which also implies
- 3. That if the factory continues to pollute, the resorts
have no incentive to switch to riding if there are no
transactions, but ...
- 4. The factory can pay them to do so, and will if it is
efficient (if the cost of switching is less than damage done
and less than cost of pollution control). No public good
problem--the ones that don't agree will continue to collect
damages until they do.
- D. Resorts have a property right--any
resort can enjoin the factory from polluting.
-
- 1. If it is efficient for the factory to pollute, with
no transactions they won't be able to, and ...
- 2. With transactions, there is a holdout problem in
getting permission from the resorts. Any single resort can
block the deal by refusing its permission, so some may try
to get a big share of the gain by threatening to block, so
the deal may fall through.
- E. Resorts can enjoin--but must pay damages
equal to the cost that doing so imposes on the factory.
Implications are left as an exercise for the reader--homework
not to be turned in.
- F. Damage payment vs fine:
- 1. Damage payment eliminates the opportunity for
strategic behavior by the factory. If the factory wants to
keep polluting, the resorts will be happy to keep operating
as fishing resorts--and suing the factory for their losses.
- a. This solves a problem that arises because of the
one vs many nature of the situation.
- b. In 1 vs 1, resort is in as good a position to be
strategic as factory.
- c. In many vs many, each factory knows that its
decision has little effect on the resorts, so it doesn't
pay to try to behave strategically.
- d. Consider driving dangerously for strategic
reasons--so that other people will drive very carefully,
or leave the road to you. One driver is such a small part
of the environment faced by other drivers that it doesn't
pay him to modify his behavior to try to affect theirs.
- e. But ... a friend of mine followed a policy of not
taking dents out of her car, on the theory that other
drivers would conclude that it was prudent for them to be
careful near her, since she didn't seem to care. So it
may become a 1 vs 1 interaction at the last moment.
- 2. Damage payments also eliminate the incentive of the
"victim" who is being compensated to eliminate the problem
himself if there are no transactions.
- 3. And a fine leads to a "double incentive" problem if
there are transactions.
- a. Go back to the resort/factory problem, assume a
fine, small number of resorts.
- b. Pollution damage = $1,000,000/year, control costs
$1,500,000/year, riding resorts not an option.
- c. Without transaction, the factory keeps on
polluting, but ...
- d. Resorts offer to pay the factory another $600,000
to stop polluting.
- e. The factory stops.
- f. Coase + Pigou is too much incentive.
- XI: Ways in which a
court might think about dealing with externalities:
- A. The central planning approach:
- 1. Decide whether it is efficient for the factory to
pollute.
- 2. If the answer is yes, dismiss the resorts' lawsuit
against the factory.
- 3. If the answer is no, either make the factory liable
or grant an injunction forbidding it from polluting
- 4. But this requires the court to know enough to figure
out whether it is efficient for the factory to pollute.
- 5. And the right answer might be neither "pollute" nor
"don't pollute" but some reduction in pollution, along with
some adjustment by the resorts.
- B. The Pigouvian approach:
- 1. Decide which party is the lower cost avoider of the
problem (which does not require you to know whether it is
worth avoiding the problem).
- 2. Make that party liable for the cost of the problem.
- 3. And leave it to him to decide whether to avoid the
problem or pay damages.
- C. The Coaseian approach:
- 1. Consider the different ways the initial rights might
be defined.
- 2. And the different outcomes that might be efficient.
- 3. And how easily, given transaction cost problems, one
could get from each initial definition of rights to each
outcome.
- 4. And how likely it is that each outcome will be the
efficient one
- 5. And choose your starting point accordingly--the one
from which it is relatively easy to get to the outcomes that
are likely to be efficient.
- 6. More precisely, consider that the cost of the problem
is the transactional cost of solving it if it is solved or
the inefficiency resulting from not solving it if it is not
solved, and choose the starting point that minimizes the
expected cost.
- XII: Property Rules
vs Liability Rules: An application of the Coasian
approach.
- A. If I want to
- 1. use your car to drive somewhere, I borrow, buy, or
rent it.
- 2. If I want to "use" your car by running into it, I do
so and you sue me.
- B. Think of these as two different ways of
handling the externalities/incompatible uses problem.
- 1. The property approach: The owner gets to decide how
his property is used, and if it is valuable to someone else
to use it, the someone else gets the owner's permission.
- 2. The liability approach. Anyone can use the
property--and owes the owner damage payments for any cost
imposed on him.
- C. Note that property rules don't just
enforce themselves, so another way of putting it is that
- 1. under liability rules, the purpose of damages is to
produce the efficient level of use directly (i.e. Pigouvian
approach);
- 2. under a property rule, the purpose of damages is to
force the transaction onto the market, and have the
efficient level produced by market transactions.
- D. In our recent discussion of the factory
and the resorts, property rules were
- 1. absolute right (the factory can pollute if he wants
to, so if the resorts object, they must persuade him not to)
or
- 2. injunctive right (the factory cannot pollute without
permission from the resort)
- 3. The difference being that in the former case the
right is held by the person with physical control over the
action, so no legal procedure is needed in order to
implement it. In the latter case, the right is held by
someone else, so he must go to court to forbid the person
with physical control from acting.
- E. Why would we choose one rule or the
other?
- 1. A property rule makes sense if transaction costs for
reallocating the right are low--the case on ordinary
markets, where people can freely buy and sell their
property.
- 2. A liability rule makes sense if transaction costs are
high:
- a. auto accidents, since you can't contract in
advance with every other driver for permission to impose
a risk on them.
- b. A lost hunter who finds a locked cabin and breaks
in--high transaction costs because the owner can't be
found in time.
- c. Pollution with many small victims
- d. What about costs imposed on one neighbor? There is
a bilateral monopoly bargaining problem if the difference
between cost imposed and cost of controlling is likely to
be very large.
- 3. Another relevant factor is how easily a court can
measure damages. If it is very hard, then the property
solution might be better even with substantial transaction
costs. That is how we handle many bilateral monopoly
cases--the purchase of a tract of land that is very valuable
to only one purchaser, for example.
- 4. A third possible rule is the central planning
solution: The court (or the government) transfers the right
to the person they think values it most, typically the
government--the military draft, for example, or jury duty.
- a. Note that this requires even more court
information than the liability rule--and creates a
greater incentive to spend resources litigating.
- b. Imagine that the way I got a house was to persuade
a court that it was worth more to me than to anyone
else--at which point it was mine for free.
- c. As opposed to the liability method--I seize the
house, and the court makes me pay its value to the
previous owner, or ...
- d. The property method--which is the one we actually
use.
- e. One reason we don't use either the property or the
liability approach for (private) slavery is that we are
pretty sure the efficient bundling is for me to own
myself.
- F. All of this is really an application of
the Coaseian approach:
- 1. The legal system uses property rules when that
minimizes the problem of getting goods to their highest
valued use.
- 2. It uses liability rules when that minimizes ...
- XIII: Insurance
issues.
- A. Why we discuss them here: Because issues
of allocating risk show up in legal rules all the time.
- 1. When there is an auto accident, who compensates whom?
- 2. When a bottle of coke explodes and injures you, is
Coca Cola liable?
- 3. When a contract breaks down because of unanticipated
problems, which party bears the cost?
- B. Why insure?
- 1. Risk aversion
- 2. aka declining marginal utility of income.
- 3. Suppose I face a 50% chance of an income of $10,000
for next year, and a 50% chance of $110,000.
- a. I expect that dollars will buy me much more
important goods if I have only $10,000 of them than if I
have $110,000, so I would like to "transfer" money from
the one state of the world to the other.
- b. Which I do by betting someone $50,000 that I am
going to have an income of only $10,000 next year.
- c. Now if I win my bet I have
$10,000+$50,000=$$60,000 and if I lose I have
$110,000-$50,000=$60,000; I prefer that lottery to the
one I started with.
- d. In other words, I have insured against a low
income.
- C. Why not insure--part I: Moral
hazard
- 1. You will take inefficiently low precautions if you
have insured your factory against fire.
- 2. More generally--we are creating an externality by
transferring the cost of my poor precautions to the
insurance company.
- 3. We can reduce the problem by coinsurance--the
insurance company only pays part of the loss.
- a. This solves most of the problem if most of the
precautions worth taking are cheap ones--still worth
taking when I only bear part of the cost of a fire.
- b. It doesn't do so well if the important
precaustions are expensive--only worth taking if I get
most of the benefit.
- c. We can also increase the probability of fire a lot
by insuring for more than 100%
- 4. But this might sometime be a feature rather than a
bug! Suppose the insurance company knows more than I do
about preventing fire, and requires me to take its advice as
a condition of insurance.
- a. I once read an article that claimed there was an
extensive literature on safety engineering for many
dangerous activities, such as chemcial companies--driven
by insurance companies
- b. But no such literature for nuclear
reactors--because they are insured primarily by the
government
- c. With the result that reactor control rooms are
designed to impress local government officials whose pe
support is needed to build the reactor, not professional
safety engineers working for insurance companies--and end
up looking like a set for a science fiction movie.
- d. I don't know if this is true--but it could be.
- 6. We are back with Coase--the loss is jointly caused,
and we want to give both parties the right incentives.
- 7. Consider the coke bottle which exploded because I was
emphasizing a rhetorical point on a hot summer day by
shaking my hand--with the bottle in it.
- D. Why not insure--part II: Adverse
selection.
- 1. Market for lemons story.
- a. $8000 cream puffs, $4000 lemons, sellers know
which are which, buyers don't, half the cars whose owners
would like to sell them if they can get a reasonable
price are each.
- b. Do they all sell for $6000? Then owners of lemons
would unload even if they don't really want to sell them,
but very few creampuffs would sell, so ...
- c. Average car sold at $6000 is almost certainly a
lemon, so not worth $6000, so price will be lower, so ...
- d. An equilibrium where price is a little about
$4000, reflecting the existence of a few creampuff owners
who badly want to get rid of their cars, and almost all
the cars sold are lemons.
- e. This is an example of market failure since lots of
owners of creampuffs value their cars at less than the
buyer does, but can't sell.
- f. Solution--guarantee the car. But ...
- g. That produces a moral hazard problem on the other
side, since it reduces the buyer's incentive to take
precautions.
- h. The two objectives are in tension, since from a
moral hazard standpoint the risk should be born by the
buyer, from an adverse selection standpoint by the
seller.
- i. My friend Ami Glazer exploited a different version
of the same principle, by finding a used car dealer who
was willing, for an additional payment, to guarantee the
car he was selling--then buying the car without the
guarantee.
- 2. Insurance story:
- a. "I want life insurance right now." Don't
sell it to him.
- b. More generally, good risks end up underinsured,
bad risks end up overinsured.
- c. Tension between who has the assymetric information
(buyer) and who can best risk spread (seller)
- D. The difficulty of solving two or three
problems at once.
- 1. We will be seeing this problem again in the context
of contract law.
- a. Buyer and seller of coke bottles both affect the
chance of an explosion
- b. Each starts with some specialized knowledge.
- c. Seller can risk spread best.
- d. Note that one solution is to figure out who was
"at fault"--but that isn't always easy.
- 2. Sometimes you can construct an ingenious solution:
- a. Robin Hanson's health care scheme: You decide how
much your life is worth. Buy that much life insurance,
from a company which will then provide you medical care
at its expense. Now resell the excess life insurance to a
second company, so as not to end up with insurance you
don't want. The first company has an incentive to figure
out what medical care is worth having, given the value of
your life to you (and it). Make sure the two companies
can't communicate, and the second doesn't know who you
are--since it is now in their interest for you to die.
- b. We are creating one market to solve the moral
hazard problem, another to solve the risk spreading
problem.
- 3. Another example of this problem we will come back to
is the difference, in tort law, between optimal damages to
deter behavior and optimal damages to insure the victim.
- XIV: Ex ante/ex post
enforcement.
- A. Auto example: speed limit or liability
for accidents.
- B. More generally: Punish by outcome or
punish by observing inputs to the production of bad outcomes,
and charging for them.
- C. Advantage of ex post:
- 1. Utilizes private information of actor re what he is
doing and its consequences. The most dangerous thing I do
while driving is to think--about things other than the
driving.
- 2. Only have to litigate when an accident happens.
- 3. At which point the damage is there to be measured.
- D. Advantage of ex ante:
- 1. Utilizes the legislator's knowledge--but why can't he
transmit that directly by telling drivers what speed is
dangerous (or whatever)?
- a. Maybe they won't believe him.
- b. But this seems to assume predictable
irrationality--which is a bad idea in economics.
- 2. Don't have to measure damage each time--just estimate
expected value.
- 3. Permits much smaller punishments. Less litigation
cost per case, plus ...
- 4. More efficient punishment--a lot of $100 fines
instead of occasionally hanging someone.
- E. Things that are not advantages but might
seem to be.
- 1. "Deter vs punish." But both methods deter.
- 2. Utilize private information about how important it is
to drive fast (or whatever)--both methods do that.
- a. With ex ante, I decide whether it is worth
it to me to risk the fine.
- b. With ex post, I decide whether it is worth
it to me to risk the accident, and the resulting costs.
- XV:
Review:
- A. Insurance and the multiple margin
problem:
- 1. Typically insoluble with a single variable--optimal
product liability.
- 2. Sometimes soluble by adding a second market--tort
plus insurance.
- 3. Or a second mechanism: Product liability with well
informed consumers.
- 4. But ... lots of problems left:
- a. The fine is both the punishment for a tort and the
incentive to sue.
- b. A damage payment affects the incentives of both
"tortfeasor" and "victim."
- c. Solving b gets back to a--criminal punishment
eliminates victim's incentive to report the accident.
- B. Ex post/Ex ante punishment:
- 1. Punishment cost, inefficiency.
- 2. The basic argument. Implies that we will almost
always use ex post for small offenses.
- 3. Why punish attempts? Ex post for ex ante for ex post.
Because of punishment costs.
- 4. General point--in a world of costless enforcement,
punishment is merely a pricing mechanism.
- a. In a world of costly enforcement, the arguments
become more complicated.
- b. There is a balance of pricing and preventing
- c. both because there are some efficient offenses,
and because whether it is worth the cost of deterring an
offense depends on how much it costs to do so and how
much damage the offense does.
- XVI: Rent
Seeking
- A. Homesteading story.
- 1. If I get ownership of 160 acres of government land by
being the first person to farm it for X years, there is an
incentive to start farming prematurely--losing money on the
farming in exchange for obtaining ownership of valuable
land. If I wait until the land is worth farming, someone
else will already be there.
- 2. So the land gets settled prematurely--early enough so
that the losses during the early years just balance the
value of ending up with the land.
- 3. Implying that the homesteading act wiped out the land
value of much of the U.S.
- 4. The analysis becomes a little more complicated if you
take account of the fact that different potential
homesteaders have different costs for homesteading, so that
it is only the marginal homesteader who gets no net gain
from homesteading.
- 5. And the actual history of thepublic lands prior to
the homesteading act suggests that there are serious
problems with the obvious alternative of auctioning the land
off.
- a. When the land is opened for homesteading there are
already settlers living on it illegally.
- b. They petition congress to led them buy "their
land" at the minimal auction price.
- c. And if congress doesn't agree, they use local
pressure to rig the auction, so as to make sure that each
settler gets the 160 acres containing the five or ten
acres he is actually farming for the minimal auction
price.
- B. General principle: If I can spend
resources on making sure that I get some valuable right instead
of someone else getting it, I will. If there are lots of
potential claimants, they will compete for the right until, on
average, the cost of getting it equals its value--at which
point their rent seeking expenditures have canceled out the
benefit of the right--the land value of much of the U.S. in the
homesteading case.
- C. Litigation implication.
- 1. When I spend money litigating, the object is to get a
damage payment at someone else's expense; and his object is
to keep me from doing so.
- 2. So both of us are engaging in a form of rent
seeking--although not with free entry into the business.
- 3. So there is no reason to expect an efficient level of
expenditure on litigation.
- D. Legislation implication:
- 1. If you have a system that transfers money to members
of a particular group, that gives people an incentive to
join that group, even if doing so is costly, which reduces
the net benefit received by those who collect the money.
- a. Obvious example--turning down a not very
attractive job in order to collect welfare benefits.
- b. Less obvious example: A law paying $10,000/year to
anyone who is legally blind. Nobody is likely to become
blind in order to collect--but someone who is almost
blind might decide to declare himself legally blind--at
the cost of not being able to get a job that his actual
eyesight is sufficient to do.
- 2. In addition, groups have an incentive to spend
resources lobbying to get and to prevent such transfers.
- E. Crime
implication:
- 1. What is wrong with theft anyway--economically
speaking? Isn't it just a transfer?
- 2. No. The opportunity to steal gives thieves an
incentive to spend resources on stealing.
- a. The marginal thief ends up leaving a job that pays
$20,000 in order to spend his time stealing $20,001.
- b. The thief gains $1, the victims lose $20,000
- c. And what is stolen is often worth more to the
victim than to the thief (goods rather than money)
- d. And there is the additional cost of precautions to
prevent theft.
- e. So on net theft reduces the total size of the pie.
- F. Another way of putting this is that rent
seeking involves inefficiencies due to negative
externalities--one consequence of my homesteading the land is
that it isn't there for you to homestead.
- XVII: Strategic
Behavior
- A. Bilateral
monopoly.
- 1. Economic example: I have the only apple, worth $1 to
me. You are the only customer, and value it at $2. If we can
agree on a price, there is a net gain of $1 to be divided
between us, with the division implied by the price.
- 2. My six-year-old threatens to throw a tantrum if she
doesn't get her way. Doing so imposes net costs, so there is
a gain to finding some mutually acceptable outcome. Don't
assume you can simply be firm and always win. You may have
thought out the logic of bilateral monopoly bargaining
better than she has, but she has a hundred million years of
evolution on her side--during which offspring who succeeded
in getting a larger share of parental resources were more
likely to survive to reproduce.
- 3. Doomsday machine.
- a. The idea. Lots of very dirty bombs buried under
the Rockies. If the Russians attack, the bombs go off and
the fallout kills everyone on earth. So the Russians
won't attack, and we don't need to pay for nuclear arms.
- b. The reality: Our (and their) nuclear systems were
doomsday machines, with human triggers. They worked, and
therefore were not used--fortunately.
- 4. Bully: If you train yourself to punch out anyone who
gets in your way, and people know it, they will stay out of
your way, and you don't have to fulfill the
commitment--until you run into someone else following the
same strategy, and one of you ends up dead. A doomsday
machine on the individual level.
- 5. In general, the outcome of such games depends largely
on issues of commitment and reputation, which are hard to
include in our analysis.
- B. For more on game theory, see the
game
theory chapter in Price
Theory.
Next
Section of the Notes
Table of
Contents
Back
to the class home page